Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-5nwft Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-05-22T22:48:38.560Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

On indefinite descriptions1

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  12 June 2009

Villy Rouchota*
Affiliation:
University College London
*
Department of Phonetics and Linguistics, University College London, Gower Street, London WC1E 6BT, UK. E-mail: villy@ling.ucl.ac.uk

Abstract

This paper explores some aspects of the semantics and pragmatics of indefinite descriptions. It is often noted that indefinite descriptions may be interpreted in several ways: attributively, referentially, specifically, generically, etc. I argue that indefinite descriptions are not semantically ambiguous and that their various interpretations are better explained on the basis of general communicative principles. Assuming an unambiguous semantics, I develop a pragmatic account of the attributive, the specific and the referential interpretation, placed within the framework of relevance theory. I compare this analysis to a Gricean one and argue that the relevance theoretic account is more adequate. Finally, I show that the proposed analysis can be extended to account for the generic and the predicative interpretations as well.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 1994

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

1

I would like to express my thanks to Robyn Carston, Deirdre Wilson and Neil Smith for their insightful comments on earlier drafts of this paper. I am also grateful to two anonymous JL referees for their comments. Finally, I would like to thank the State Scholarship Foundation in Greece for financially supporting my research at UCL.

References

REFERENCES

Barwise, J. & Perry, J. (1983). Situations and attitudes. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Blakemore, D. (1992). Understanding utterances: an introduction to pragmatics. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Carston, R. (1988). Explicature, implicature and truth theoretic semantics. In Kempson, R. (ed.) Mental representations: the interface between language and reality. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. 155181.Google Scholar
Carston, R. (1993). Conjunction and pragmatic effects. In The encyclopaedia of language and linguistics. Pergamon Press and the Aberdeen University Press.Google Scholar
Chastain, C. (1975). Reference and context. In Gunderson, K. (ed.) Language, mind and knowledge. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press. 194269.Google Scholar
Christophersen, P. (1939). The articles: a study of their theory and use in English. Copenhagen: Munksgaard.Google Scholar
Cohen, L. J. (1971). Some remarks on Grice's views about the logical particles of natural language. In Bar-Hillel, Y. (ed.) Pragmatics of natural language. Dordrecht: Reidel. 5068.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Donnellan, K. (1966/1977). Reference and definite descriptions. In Schwartz, S. (ed.) (1977). Naming, necessity and natural kinds. Cornell: Cornell University Press. 4265. (Reprinted from The Philosophical Review 75. 281–304.)Google Scholar
Donnellan, K. (1978). Speaker reference, descriptions and anaphora. In Cole, P. (ed.) Syntax and semantics 9: Pragmatics. New York: Academic Press. 4768.Google Scholar
Farkas, D. (1985). Intensional descriptions and the Romance subjunctive mood. New York: Garland Publishing, Inc.Google Scholar
Fodor, J. D. & Sag, I. (1982). Referential and quantificational indefinites. Linguistics and Philosophy 5. 355398.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Grice, H. P. (1969). Vacuous names. In Davidson, D. & Hintikka, J. (eds.) Words and objections: essays on the work of W. V. Quine. Dordrecht: Reidel. 118145.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Grice, H. P. (1975/1989). Logic and conversation. In Grice, H. P. (1989). Studies in the way of words. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. 2240. (Reprinted from Cole, P. & Morgan, J. (eds.) (1975). Syntax and semantics 3. New York: Academic Press. 41–58.)Google Scholar
Hall-Partee, B. (1972). Opacity, coreference and pronouns. In Davidson, D. & Harman, G. (eds.) Semantics of natural language. Dordrecht: Reidel. 415441.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Heim, I. (1982). The semantics of definite and indefinite noun phrases. Ph.D. dissertation, Graduate School of the University of Massachusetts.Google Scholar
Heim, I. (1983). File change semantics and the familiarity theory of definiteness. In Bauerle, R., Schwarze, C. & von Stechow, A. (eds.) Meaning, use and interpretation of language. Berlin: de Grutyer. 164189.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jespersen, O. (1949). A Modern English grammar. (Vol. VII.) Copenhagen: Munksgaard.Google Scholar
Kamp, H. (1984). A theory of truth and semantic representation. In Groenendijk, J., Janssen, T. M. V. & Stokhof, M. (eds.) Truth, interpretation and information. Dordrecht: Foris. 142.Google Scholar
Kartunnen, L. (1976). Discourse referents. In McCawley, J. (ed.). Syntax and semantics 7: Notes from the linguistic underground. New York: Academic Press. 363386.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kempson, R. (1986). Definite NPs and context-dependence: a unified theory of anaphora. In Travis, C. (ed.) Meaning and interpretation. Oxford: Blackwell. 209239.Google Scholar
Kempson, R. (1990). Anaphora: a unitary account. In Proceedings of the Portugal Linguistics Association Meeting, 10 1990.Google Scholar
Kempson, R. (forthcoming). Language and cognition: licensing grammar. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
King, J. C. (1988). Are indefinite descriptions ambiguous? Philosophical Studies 53. 417440.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kripke, S. (1977). Speaker's reference and semantic reference. In French, P. A., Uehling, T. E. & Wettstein, H. K. (eds.) Contemporary perspectives in the philosophy of language. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press. 627.Google Scholar
Ludlow, P. & Neale, S. (1991). Indefinite descriptions: in defense of Russell. Linguistics and Philosophy 14. 171202.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Neale, S. (1990). Descriptions. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Nunberg, G. & Pan, C. (1975). Inferring quantification in generic structures. In Grossman, R. E., San, J. L. & Vance, T. J. (eds.) Papers from the Eleventh Regional Meeting of the Chicago Linguistics Society. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. 412422.Google Scholar
Recanati, F. (1989 a). Referential/attributive: a contextualist proposal. Philosophical Studies 56. 217249.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Recanati, F. (1989 b). The pragmatics of what is said. Mind and Language 4. 295329.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Recanati, F. (1993). Direct reference: from language to thought. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Rouchota, V. (1992). On the referential/attributive distinction. Lingua 87. 137167.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rouchota, V. (1994). The semantics and pragmatics of the subjunctive in Modern Greek: a relevance theoretic approach. Ph.D. dissertation, University College London.Google Scholar
Russell, B. (1905). On denoting. Mind 14. 479493.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Russell, B. (1919). Introduction to mathematical philosophy. London: George Allen & Unwin.Google Scholar
Searle, J. (1979). Referential and attributive. Monist 62. 190208.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sperber, D. & Wilson, D. (1986). Relevance: communication and cognition. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Sperber, D. & Wilson, D. (1987). A précis of relevance, presumptions of relevance and open peer commentary. Behavioural and Brain Sciences 10. 697754.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stich, S. (1986). Are belief predicates systematically ambiguous? In Bogdan, R. J. (ed.) Belief. Oxford: Clarendon Press. 119147.Google Scholar
Strawson, P. F. (1950). On referring. Mind 59. 320344.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Strawson, P. F. (1952). Introduction to logical theory. London: Methuen.Google Scholar
Wilson, D. (1991). Varieties of non-truth-conditional meaning. Ms., University College London.Google Scholar
Wilson, D. (to appear). Reference and relevance. In Munch, B. & Posner, R. (eds.) Proceedings of the International Semiotics Conference on Reference.Google Scholar
Wilson, D. & Sperber, D. (1981). On Grice's theory of conversation. In Werth, P. (ed.) Conversation and discourse. London: Croom Helm. 155178.Google Scholar
Wilson, D. & Sperber, D. (1993). Linguistic form and relevance. Lingua 90. 125.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wilson, G. (1978). On definite and indefinite descriptions. The Philosophical Review 87. 4876.CrossRefGoogle Scholar