Hostname: page-component-76fb5796d-45l2p Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-29T05:32:51.170Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

A HISTORICAL ATLAS OF OBJECTIVITY

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  09 November 2009

MI GYUNG KIM*
Affiliation:
Department of History, North Carolina State University E-mail: migkim@gw.ncsu.edu

Extract

The mythical scientist in early twentieth-century America cut a lone figure, “impersonal as the chill northeast wind” and “oblivious of everything save his experiment.” He toiled through the night in his laboratory, “a place unimpressive and unmagical save for the constant-temperature bath with its tricky thermometer and electric bulbs,” as if working in the lab were a prayer that promised illumination—“alone, absorbed, [and] contemptuous of academic success and of popular classes,” he knew all about material forces, but he was blind to the vital force that created all others. Accustomed to the “beautiful dullness of long labors,” he remained “illimitably ignorant” of literature, art, and music. He believed that unerring techniques in experimentation, impartial observations, and exquisitely minute calculations would bring progress—a steady march toward the truth. He chose the highest calling in the world because he was “intensely religious—so religious that he will not accept quarter-truths, because they are an insult to his faith.” He was “so devoted to Pure Science . . . that he would rather have people die by the right therapy than be cured by the wrong. Having built a shrine for humanity, he wanted to kick out of it all mere human beings.” This autocratic figure, brilliantly insane and tyrannically honest, embodied the cult of science and objectivity.

Type
Essay
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 2009

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 Peter Dear argues that the Popperian notion of objectivity invokes “a kind of shadow-world that only exists by virtue of those things that it is not” or by the negation of subjectivity. Dear, P., “From Truth to Disinterestedness in the Seventeenth Century,” Social Studies of Science 22 (1992), 619–31CrossRefGoogle Scholar; original emphasis.

2 S. Lewis, Arrowsmith, first published in 1925.

3 According to Thomas E. Willey, “Neo-Kantianism emerged in the late 1850s and early 1860s [as a response to “naive scientism” and materialism], achieved academic supremacy in the 1890s, and rapidly lost its academic preeminence (but not its entire following) after 1914.” T. E. Willey, Back to Kant: The Revival of Kantianism in German Social and Historical Thought, 1860–1914 (Detroit, 1978), 21. The authors do not use the term “neo-Kantian” or engage with Kant's epistemology.

4 Hannaway, O., The Chemists and the Word: The Didactic Origins of Chemistry (Baltimore, 1975)Google Scholar.

5 I. Scheffler, Science and Subjectivity (Indianapolis, 1967), 1.

6 Keller, E. F., Reflections on Gender and Science (New Haven, 1985)Google Scholar; Rorty, R., Objectivity, Relativism, and Truth (Cambridge, 1991)Google Scholar; Haraway, D., “Situated Knowledges: The Science Question in Feminism and the Privilege of Partial Perspective,” Feminist Studies 14 (1988), 575–99CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

7 Daston, L., “Baconian Facts, Academic Civility, and the Prehistory of Objectivity,” in Megill, A., ed., Rethinking Objectivity (Durham, NC., 1994), 3763Google Scholar; idem, “Preternatural Philosophy,” in Daston, L., ed., Biographies of Scientific Objects (Chicago, 2000), 1541Google Scholar.

8 Dear, P., Discipline and Experience: The Mathematical Way in the Scientific Revolution (Chicago, 1995)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

9 Tiles, M. and Tiles, J., An Introduction to Historical Epistemology: The Authority of Knowledge (Oxford, 1993)Google Scholar.

10 Solomon, J. R., Objectivity in the Making: Francis Bacon and the Politics of Inquiry (Baltimore, 1998)Google Scholar, xiv; Harkness, D. E., The Jewel House: Elizabethan London and the Scientific Revolution (New Haven, 2007), 211–53Google Scholar.

11 Megill, Rethinking Objectivity, 1–20; Zagorin, P., “Francis Bacon's Concept of Objectivity and the Idols of the Mind,” British Journal for the History of Science 34 (2001), 379–93CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

12 Particularly influential works in this regard are Shapin, Steven and Schaffer, Simon, Leviathan and the Air-Pump (Chicago, 1985)Google Scholar; Shapin, Steven, A Social History of Truth: Civility and Science in Seventeenth-Century England (Chicago, 1994)Google Scholar.

13 Foucault, M., The Hermeneutics of the Subject (New York, 2005)CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Goldstein, J., The Postrevolutionary Self: Politics and Psyche in France, 1750–1850 (Cambridge, MA, 2005)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

14 Smith, C. and Wise, M. N., Energy and Empire: A Biographical Study of Lord Kelvin (Cambridge, 1989)Google Scholar; Terrall, Mary, The Man Who Flattened the Earth: Maupertuis and the Sciences in the Enlightenment (Chicago, 2002)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

15 Merton, R. K., “The Normative Structure of Science (1942),” in Storer, N. W., ed., The Sociology of Science: Theoretical and Empirical Investigations (Chicago, 1973), 267–78Google Scholar; Prelli, L. J., “The Rhetorical Construction of Scientific Ethos,” in Simons, H. W., ed., Rhetoric in the Human Sciences (London, 1989), 4868Google Scholar.

16 Schaffer, Simon, “Astronomers Mark Time: Discipline and the Personal Equation,” Science in Context 2 (1988), 115–45CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

17 For Kant's role in forging “philosophy-as-epistemology” see Rorty, R., Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature (Princeton, 1979), 131–64Google Scholar. The words Erkenntnislehre and Erkenntnistheorie were invented in 1808 and 1832 respectively, the latter only after the Hegelian system was discredited by empirical research. H.-G. Gadamer, Truth and Method (New York, 1993) (Translation of Wahrheit und Methode (1960)), 220.

18 E. B. de Condillac, An Essay on the Origin of Human Knowledge (New York, 1974) (translation of Essai sur l'origine des connaissances humaines (1746)), 2–3; added emphasis; cf. idem, “A Treatise on Systems,” in Philosophical Writings of Etienne Bonnot, Abbé de Condillac (London, 1982), 1–153.

19 Condillac, Essay, 5–6.

20 Ibid., 333.

21 I. Kant, Prolegomena (1783), in J. W. Ellington, ed., Immanuel Kant: Philosophy of Material Nature (Indianapolis, 1985), 1–7; Watkins, Eric, Kant and the Metaphysics of Causality (Cambridge, 2005)Google Scholar.

22 Kant, I., The Critique of Pure Reason (New York, 1965)Google Scholar, Preface and Introduction. Many thanks to Professor John Zammito for pointing out the importance of understanding in Kant's Critique.

23 Dickerson, A. B., Kant on Representation and Objectivity (Cambridge, 2004)Google Scholar; Mittelstaedt, P., “The Constitution of Objects in Kant's Philosophy and in Modern Physics,” in Parrini, P., ed., Kant and Contemporary Epistemology (Dordrecht, 1994), 115–29CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

24 Beiser, F. C., “Kant's Intellectual Development: 1746–1781,” in Guyer, P., ed., The Cambridge Companion to Kant (Cambridge, 1992), 2661CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

25 Simons, H. W., ed., The Rhetorical Turn: Invention and Persuasion in the Conduct of Inquiry (Chicago, 1990)CrossRefGoogle Scholar; J. S. Nelson et al., eds., The Rhetoric of the Human Sciences: Language and Argument in Scholarship and Public Affairs (Madison, WI, 1987).

26 I. Newton, Principia (1687), Preface; idem, Opticks (1704), Query 31.

27 Calinger, R., “Kant and Newtonian Science: The Pre-critical Period,” Isis 70 (1977), 349–62CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Friedman, M., Kant and the Exact Sciences (Cambridge, MA, 1992)Google Scholar.

28 For the “homology between the world and the rational subject” which fashioned the autonomy of the Kantian self see J. Seigel, The Idea of the Self (Cambridge, 2005), 295–331.

29 M. Friedman and A. Nordmann, eds., The Kantian Legacy in Nineteenth-Century Science (Cambridge, MA, 2006). K. C. Köhnke, The Rise of Neo-Kantianism: German Academic Philosophy between Idealism and Positivism (Cambridge, 1991).

30 Rhetoric as a “ritual use of words” to indicate political commitments, thereby engendering or constituting political practice and culture, is analyzed in L. Hunt, Politics, Culture and Class in the French Revolution (Berkeley, CA, 1984).

31 Willey, Back to Kant.

32 Novick points out how strongly idealistic Ranke in fact was. For the poetic dimension of European historical writing see Hayden White, Metahistory: The Historical Imagination in Nineteenth-Century Europe (Baltimore, 1973), 163–90.

33 Novick, P., That Noble Dream: The “Objectivity Question” and the American Historical Profession (Cambridge, 1988), 160CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

34 L. Fleck, Genesis and Development of a Scientific Fact (Chicago, 1979) (translation of Entstehung und Entwicklung einer wissenschaftlichen Tatsache: Einführung in die Lehre vom Denkstil und Denkkollektiv (Basel, 1935)); Kuhn, T. S., The Structure of Scientific Revolutions (Chicago, 1962)Google Scholar.

35 Ash, M. G., Gestalt Psychology in German Culture, 1890–1967: Holism and the Quest for Objectivity (Cambridge, 1995)Google Scholar.

36 Lenoir, T., Instituting Science: The Cultural Production of Scientific Disciplines (Stanford, 1997)Google Scholar.

37 Kim, M. G., “Labor and Mirage: Writing the History of Chemistry,” Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 26 (1995), 155–65CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

38 Yeo, R. R., Defining Science: William Whewell, Natural Knowledge, and Public Debate in Early Victorian Britain (Cambridge, 1993)CrossRefGoogle Scholar; C. Jungnickel and R. McCormmach, Intellectual Mastery of Nature: Theoretical Physics from Ohm to Einstein, 2 vols. (Chicago, 1986).

39 W. Ostwald, Abhandlungen und Vorträge (Leipzig, 1916), 185–206.

40 Gadamer, Truth and Method, 3–9.

41 H. von Helmholtz, “On the Relation of Natural Science to Science in General,” in David Cahan, ed., Science and Culture: Popular and Philosophical Essays (Chicago, 1995), 76–95 (translation of “Ueber das Verhältnis der Naturwissenschaften zur Gesamtheit der Wissenschaften (1862)”).

42 Dilthey, W., Introduction to the Human Sciences (Princeton, 1989)Google Scholar, 56–8 (Einleitung in die Geisteswissenschaften: Versuch einer Grundlegung für das Studium der Gesellschaft und der Geschichte (1883), in Gesammelte Schriften, vol. 1 (Stuttgart, 1923)); Gadamer, Truth and Method, 218–42.

43 Ringer, F., The Decline of the German Mandarins: The German Academic Community, 1890–1933 (Cambridge, MA, 1969)Google Scholar; idem, Max Weber's Methodology: The Unification of the Cultural and Social Sciences (Cambridge, MA, 1997); idem, Max Weber: An Intellectual Biography (Chicago, 2004).

44 W. Windelband, “History and Natural Science,” History and Theory 19 (1980), 165–8 (translation by G. Oakes of “Geschichte und Naturwissenschaft,” rectoral address at Strasbourg, 1894).

45 Lamprecht, K., Deutsche Geschichte, 12 vols. (Berlin, 1891–1909)Google Scholar; Chickering, R., Karl Lamprecht: A German Academic Life (1856–1915) (Atlantic Highlands, NJ, 1993)Google Scholar.

46 Kim, M. G., “Wilhelm Ostwald (1853–1932),” Hyle 12 (2006), 141–8Google Scholar.

47 M. Weber, “‘Objectivity’ in Social Science and Social Policy,” in Max Weber on the Methodology of the Social Sciences, trans. E. A. Shils and H. A. Finch (The Free Press, 1949), 49–112; original emphasis (“Die ‘Objectivität’ sozialwissenschaftlicher und sozial politischer Erkenntnis (1904),” in idem, Gesammelte Aufsätze zur Wissenschaftslehre (Tübingen, 1922), 146–214).

48 Weber, “Objectivity,” 57–8; “Objektivität,” 154–5. In this first part of the essay, Weber is articulating the editorial policy more than his personal view.

49 Weber, “Objectivity,” 72–3; original emphasis; “Objectivität,” 170–71. Scaff, L. A., Fleeing the Iron Cage: Culture, Politics, and Modernity in the Thought of Max Weber (Berkeley, 1989), 83–7Google Scholar.

50 G. E. McCarthy, “Max Weber and the Kantians: Epistemology and Method in the Wissenschaftslehre,” in idem, Objectivity and the Silence of Reason: Weber, Habermas, and the Methodological Disputes in German Sociology (New Brunswick, NJ, 2001), 127–212.

51 Brain, R. M., “The Ontology of the Questionnaire: Max Weber on Measurement and Mass Investigation,” Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 32 (2001), 647–84CrossRefGoogle Scholar; M. Weber, “Zur Psychophysik der Industriellen Arbeit (1908–09)” in idem, Gesammelte Aufsätze zur Soziologie und Sozialpolitik (Tübingen, 1924), 61–255.

52 Weber, M., “Energetische Kulturtheorien,” Archiv für Sozialwissenschaft und Sozialpolitik 29 (1909), 575–98Google Scholar; reprinted in idem, Gesammelte Aufsätze zur Wissenschaftslehre, 376–402.

53 Haeckel's The Riddle of the Universe (New York, 1900) (Welträthsel, gemeinverständliche Studien über monistische Philosophie (Bonn, 1899)) was a smashing success that saw seven editions within the first two years of its publication and sold 400,000 copies by World War I in Germany alone. The people's edition that cost just one mark appeared in 1903. R. J. Richards, The Tragic Sense of Life: Ernst Haeckel and the Struggle over Evolutionary Thought (Chicago, 2008), 398–403.

54 Ostwald, W., Monistische Sonntagspredigten (Leipzig, 1911)Google Scholar.

55 Mommsen, W. J., Max Weber and German Politics, 1890–1920 (Chicago, 1984)Google Scholar.

56 M. Weber, “Science as a Vocation” (1918), in From Max Weber: Essays in Sociology, ed. H. H. Gerth and C. Wright Mills (New York, 1946), 128–56, 135; original emphasis (“Wissenschaft als Beruf,” in Gesammelte Aufsätze zur Wissenschaftslehre, 524–55).

57 Ibid., 146–55.

58 Hanna, R., Kant and the Foundations of Analytic Philosophy (Oxford, 2001)Google Scholar; idem, Kant, Science, and Human Nature (Oxford, 2006).

59 G. A. Reisch, How the Cold War Transformed Philosophy of Science: To the Icy Slopes of Logic (Cambridge, 2005).

60 Polanyi, M., Personal Knowledge: Towards a Post-critical Philosophy (Chicago, 1958), 517 and 64Google Scholar; added emphasis.

61 Kuhn, The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, 1.

62 Golinski, J., Making Natural Knowledge: Constructivism and the History of Science (Cambridge, 1998)Google Scholar; Zammito, J. H., A Nice Derangement of Epistemes: Post-positivism in the Study of Science from Quine to Latour (Chicago, 2004)Google Scholar. Many thanks to Professor Robert S. Westman for this reference.

63 Kuhn, T. S., “The Relations between the History and the Philosophy of Science,” in idem, Essential Tension (Chicago, 1977), 320Google Scholar; idem, “The Trouble with the Historical Philosophy of Science” (Cambridge, MA, 1992).

64 Alpers, S., The Art of Describing: Dutch Art in the Seventeenth Century (Chicago, 1983)Google Scholar.

65 Smith, P. H., The Body of the Artisan: Art and Experience in the Scientific Revolution (Chicago, 2004)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

66 Wise, M. N., “Mediating Machines,” Science in Context 2 (1988), 77113CrossRefGoogle Scholar; idem, “Architectures for Steam,” in P. Galison and E. Thompson, eds., Architecture of Science (1999), 107–40; idem, “Staging an Empire,” in L. Daston, ed., Things that Talk (Cambridge, MA, 2004), 101–46.

67 For this resurgent concern see “Changing Directions in History and Philosophy of Science,” Isis 99 (2008), 88–134.

68 Daston, L., “On Scientific Observation,” Isis 99 (2008), 97110CrossRefGoogle Scholar; idem, Biographies of Scientific Objects.

69 Galison, P., “Ten Problems in History and Philosophy of Science,” Isis 99 (2008), 111–24CrossRefGoogle Scholar; original emphasis.

70 Radder, Hans, ed., The Philosophy of Scientific Experimentation (Pittsburgh, PA, 2003)CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Baird, D., Thing Knowledge: A Philosophy of Scientific Instruments (Berkeley, CA, 2004)Google Scholar.

71 Kim, M. G., “The ‘Instrumental’ Reality of Phlogiston,” Hyle 14 (2008), 2751Google Scholar; idem, “From Phlogiston to Caloric: Chemical Ontologies,” forthcoming in S. Mauskopf and T. Schmaltz, eds., Integrating History and Philosophy of Science (Durham, NC, 2010).

72 Kim, M. G., “The Layers of Chemical Language,” History of Science 30 (1992), 6996 and 397–437CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

73 Pickering, A., Constructing Quarks (Edinburgh, 1984)Google Scholar; Rudwick, M., The Great Devonian Controversy: The Shaping of Scientific Knowledge among Gentlemanly Specialists (Chicago, 1985)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

74 La Folie, De, Le Philosophe sans Prétention ou L'Homme rare (Paris, 1775), 88Google Scholar.

75 Priestley, J., Disquisitions Relating to Matter and Spirit and the Doctrine of Philosophical Necessity Illustrated (London, 1777)Google Scholar.

76 Shapiro, G., Archeologies of Vision: Foucault and Nietzsche on Seeing and Saying (Chicago, 2003), 6Google Scholar.

77 Nagel, T., The View from Nowhere (Oxford, 1986)Google Scholar; A. N. H. Creager et al., eds., Science without Laws: Model Systems, Cases, Exemplary Narratives (Durham, NC, 2007).

78 Heidegger, M., Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics (Bloomington, IN, 1962), 17Google Scholar.

79 Gillispie, C. C., The Edge of Objectivity: An Essay in the History of Scientific Ideas (Princeton, NJ, 1960)Google Scholar; Popper, K. R., Objective Knowledge: An Evolutionary Approach (Oxford, 1972)Google Scholar; Bloor, D., “Popper's Mystification of Objective Knowledge,” Science Studies 4 (1974), 6576CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

80 F. Bacon, New Atlantis (1626); A. Huxley, Brave New World (1932).

81 Hacking, I., Historical Ontology (Cambridge, MA, 2002)CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Sibum, H. O., ed., “Science and the Changing Senses of Reality circa 1900,” special issue, Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 39 (2008), 295458CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

82 Tiles and Tiles, An Introduction to Historical Epistemology, 5; B. Latour, “Why Has Critique Run out of Steam? From Matters of Fact to Matters of Concern,” Critical Inquiry 30 (2004), 225–48.

83 Latour, B., “When Things Strike back: A Possible Contribution of ‘Science Studies’ to the Social Sciences,” British Journal of Sociology 51 (2000), 107–23CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Brown, B., A Sense of Things: The Object Matter of American Literature (Chicago, 2003)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

84 Tobin, B. F., “Imperial Designs: Botanical Illustration and the British Botanic Empire,” Studies in Eighteenth-Century Culture 25 (1996), 265–92CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Pratt, M. L., Imperial Eyes: Travel Writing and Transculturation (London, 1992)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

85 Domanska, E., “The Material Presence of the Past,” History and Theory 45 (2006), 337–48CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

86 Jean-François Lyotard, The Postmodern Condition: A Report on Knowledge (Minneapolis, 1984).

87 Helmholtz, “On the Relation of Natural Science to Science in General,” 95.