Hostname: page-component-8448b6f56d-mp689 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-24T16:40:35.540Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

LIBERAL DISPOSITIONS: RECENT SCHOLARSHIP ON FRENCH LIBERALISM

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  20 February 2015

MICHAEL C. BEHRENT*
Affiliation:
Department of History, Appalachian State University E-mail: behrentmc@appstate.edu

Extract

The story of French liberalism is, we are often told, one of exceptions, eccentricities, and enigmas. Compared to their British counterparts, French liberals seem more reluctant to embrace individualism. Whereas liberals in the English-speaking world typically espouse what Isaiah Berlin called “negative liberty”—a sphere of private autonomy from which the state is legally excluded—French liberals have often proved highly accommodating towards “positive liberty”—that is, liberty insofar as it is tethered to collectively defined ends. Most crucially, rather than seeking to shield individuals and civil society from an intrusive state, French liberals—consistent with a broader trend in French political culture—are inclined to see the state as an essential and even emancipatory political tool. In this vein, Jean-Fabien Spitz writes in a recent collection entitled French Liberalism from Montesquieu to the Present Day,

Contemporary historians, political scientists, and philosophers all seem to share a simple idea: French political culture, marked as it is by legalism and statism, constitutes an exception to the main trend in modern political thought, which has been to discover and assert the principles of modern liberty.

In addition to departing from some of Anglo-American liberalism's main tenets, French liberalism exhibits other oddities: as Larry Siedentop argued in an important essay, its idiom has tended to be historical (rather than theoretical), institutional (as opposed to ethical) and sociological (not legal or political).2 This somewhat idiosyncratic variation on “normal” liberalism has led some scholars to characterize liberalism's French iteration as a “chaotic mixture.”3 Others have questioned the extent to which liberalism is really a significant French political tradition at all. France's Revolutionary culture has been described as ultimately “illiberal,” leading some historians to speak of a French Sonderweg,4 in which France's “special path” consists in the fact that it entered the modern age without having developed genuinely liberal institutions.

Type
Essays
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 2015 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 Spitz, Jean-Fabien, “The “Illiberalism’ of French Liberalism: The Individual and the State in the Thought of Blanc, Dupont-White and Durkheim,” trans. Michel Breslin, in Geenens, Raf and Rosenblatt, Helena, eds., French Liberalism from Montesquieu to the Present Day (Cambridge, 2012), 252–68, at 252CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

2 Larry Siedentop, “Two Liberal Traditions,” first published in Ryan, Alan, ed., The Idea of Freedom (Oxford, 1979), 153–74Google Scholar. Siedentop's essay has been republished in Geenens and Rosenblatt, French Liberalism, 15–35.

3 Guido de Ruggiero, quoted in Helena Rosenblatt, “On the Need for a Protestant Reformation: Constant, Sismondi, Guizot and Laboulaye,” in Geenens and Rosenblatt, French Liberalism, at 115.

4 Tombs, Robert, “Was there a French Sonderweg?,” European Review of History 1/2 (1994), 169–77CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

5 Craiutu, Aurelian, A Virtue for Courageous Minds: Moderation in French Political Thought, 1748–1830 (Princeton, NJ, 2012)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

6 Vincent, K. Steven, Benjamin Constant and the Birth of French Liberalism (New York, 2011), 4CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

7 Paulet-Grandguillot, Emannuelle, Libéralisme et démocratie: De Sismondi à Constant, à partir du Contrat Social (1801–1806) (Geneva, 2010)Google Scholar.

8 Earlier works on French liberalism include Martin, Kingsley, French Liberal Thought in the Eighteenth Century: A Study of Political Ideas from Bayle to Condorcet (New York, 1963)Google Scholar; Jardin, André, Histoire du libéralisme politique: De la crise de l’absolutisme à la Constitution de 1875 (Paris, 1985)Google Scholar; and Kelly, George Armstrong, The Humane Comedy: Constant, Tocqueville, and French Liberalism (Cambridge, 1992)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

9 Woloch, Isser, “On the Latent Illiberalism of the French Revolution,” American Historical Review, 95/5 (1990), 1452–70CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

10 Jaume, Lucien, L’individu effacé, ou, Le paradoxe du libéralisme français (Paris, 1997), 11Google Scholar.

11 de Dijn, Annelien, French Political Thought from Montesquieu to Tocqueville (Cambridge, 2008)CrossRefGoogle Scholar. A different take on “aristocratic liberalism”—understood as an elitist form of liberalism that is skeptical towards democracy, rather than as one that is specifically tied to the values of a landed aristocracy—is discussed in Kahan, Alan S.'s Aristocratic Liberalism: The Social and Political Thought of Jacob Burckhardt, John Stuart Mill, and Alexis de Tocqueville (New York and Oxford, 1992)Google Scholar.

12 Rosenblatt, Helena. Liberal Values: Benjamin Constant and the Politics of Religion (Cambridge, 2008)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

13 Jainchill, Andrew, Reimagining Politics after the Terror: The Republican Origins of French Liberalism (Ithaca, NY and London, 2008), 19Google Scholar.

14 Rosanvallon, Pierre, Le modèle politique français: La société civile contre le jacobinisme (Paris, 2004), 12, 13, 18Google Scholar. An engagement and development of Rosanvallon's arguments in this book can be found in Wright, Julian and Jones, H. S., eds., Pluralism and the Idea of the Republic in France (Houndmills and New York, 2012)CrossRefGoogle Scholar. On Rosanvallon's relation to Furet and revisionism see Andrew Jainchill and Samuel Moyn, “French Democracy between Totalitarianism and Solidarity: Pierre Rosanvallon and Revisionist Historiography,” Journal of Modern History 76/1 (2004), 107–54.

15 Mehta, Uday Singh, Liberalism and Empire: A Study in Nineteenth-Century British Liberal Thought (Chicago and London, 1999), 190. Mehta is paraphrasing E. P. ThompsonGoogle Scholar.

16 Pitts, Jennifer, A Turn to Empire: The Rise of Imperial Liberalism in Britain and France (Princeton, 2005), 196CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

17 Raf Geenens and Helena Rosenblatt, “French Liberalism: An Overlooked Tradition?”, in Geenens and Rosenblatt, French Liberalism, 1–12, at 3, 7, 11.

18 Ibid., 2, 9.

19 Lucien Jaume, “The Unity, Diversity, and Paradoxes of French Liberalism,” in Geenens and Rosenblatt, French Liberalism, 38–9.

20 Spitz, “The ‘Illiberalism’ of French Liberalism,” 254.

21 Pettit, Philip, Republicanism: A Theory of Freedom and Government (Oxford, 1997)Google Scholar.

22 Helena Rosenblatt, “On the Need for a Protestant Reformation: Constant, Sismondi, Guizot and Laboulaye,” in Geenens and Rosenblatt, French Liberalism, 115–33.

23 Cheryl B. Welch, “‘Anti-Benthamism’: Utilitarianism and the French Liberal Tradition,” in Geenens and Rosenblatt, French Liberalism, 134–51.

24 William Logue, “The ‘Sociological Turn’ in French Liberal Thought,” in Geenens and Rosenblatt, French Liberalism, 233–51.

25 Samuel Moyn, “The Politics of Individual Rights: Marcel Gauchet and Claude Lefort,” in Geenens and Rosenblatt, French Liberalism, 291–310, at 309.

26 Alan S. Kahan, “Tocqueville: Liberalism and Imperialism,” in Geenens and Rosenblatt, French Liberalism, 152–65, at 165.

27 Stephen Holmes, “Rethinking Liberalism and Terror,” in Geenens and Rosenblatt, French Liberalism, 90–112.

28 Geenens and Rosenblatt, “French Liberalism,” 11.

29 Craiutu, A Virtue for Courageous Minds, 15.

30 Ibid., 16, 17–18.

31 Ibid., 19, original emphasis.

32 Ibid., 27.

33 Ibid., 30.

34 Ibid., 166.

35 Ibid., 168.

36 Ibid., 14–15.

37 Ibid., 3.

38 Ibid., 106.

39 Ibid., 1.

40 Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics, in Introduction to Aristotle, ed. Richard McKeon (New York, 1947), II:1–2, 331–2.

41 Craiutu, A Virtue for Courageous Minds, 5, original emphasis.

42 Ibid., 238.

43 Ibid., 85–91.

44 Ibid., 76.

45 Ibid., 108–9.

46 Ibid., 146.

47 Craiutu, “Raymond Aron and the Tradition of Political Moderation in France,” in Geenens and Rosenblatt, French Liberalism, 271–90.

48 Vincent, Benjamin Constant, 1–2.

49 The explosion of the Constant literature began with such pioneering works as Hoffman, Etienne, Les “Principes de politique” de Benjamin Constant, 2 vols. (Geneva, 1980)Google Scholar; Gauchet, Marcel, “Benjamin Constant: L’illusion lucide du libéralisme,” in Benjamin Constant, Ecrits politiques (Paris, 1980)Google Scholar, 11–110; Holmes, Stephen, Benjamin Constant and the Making of Modern Liberalism (New Haven, 1984)Google Scholar; and Fontana, Biancamaria, Constant and the Post-Revolutionary Mind (New Haven, 1991)Google Scholar. See, too, Rosenblatt, Helena, “Why Constant? A Critical Overview of the Constant Revival,” Modern Intellectual History, 1/3 (2004), 439–53Google Scholar.

50 Vincent, Benjamin Constant, 5.

51 Ibid., 3.

52 Ibid.

53 Ibid.

54 Ibid., 25.

55 Quoted in ibid., 23.

56 Quoted in ibid., 61.

57 Ibid., 145.

58 Quoted in ibid., 144.

59 Ibid., 145.

60 Quoted in ibid., 147.

61 Ibid., 162.

62 Ibid., 55.

63 Ibid., 52.

64 Ibid.

65 Ibid., 87.

66 Ibid., 214–15.

67 Ibid., 148.

68 Ibid., 208.

69 Ibid., 210.

70 Ibid., 77.

71 Paulet-Grandguillot, Libéralisme et démocratie, 26, 26–7.

72 Quoted in ibid., 81.

73 Ibid., 101.

74 Ibid., 107.

75 Ibid., 340.

76 Ibid., 401.

77 Ibid., 404.

78 Bobbio, Norberto, “Liberals and Democrats in the Nineteenth Century,” in Bobbio, , Liberalism and Democracy, trans. Martin Ryle and Kate Soper (London and New York, 2005), 45–50, at 48–9Google Scholar.

79 On the “neo-republican” trend in French thought see Chabal, Emile's forthcoming study, A Divided Republic: Nation, State and Citizenship in Contemporary France (Cambridge, 2014)Google Scholar.

80 Spitz, “The “Illiberalism’ of French Liberalism,” 268.

81 Pettit, Republicanism; Habermas, Jürgen, “Three Normative Models of Democracy,” in Habermas, , The Inclusion of the Other: Studies in Political Theory (Cambridge, 1998), 239–52Google Scholar.

82 Breyer, Stephen, Active Liberty: Interpreting our Democratic Constitution (New York, 2005)Google Scholar.

83 A key project driven by this insight is the work of Pierre Rosanvallon. An important figure in the liberal revival of the 1970s, Rosanvallon, having written a three-volume history of French democracy, has recently completed a second trilogy that addresses democracy's contemporary evolution: La contre-démocratie: La politique à l’âge de la défiance (Paris, 2005); La légitimité démocratique: Impartialité, réflexivité, proximité (Paris, 2008); and La société des égaux (Paris, 2011).

84 Philippe Steiner, “Competition and Knowledge: French Political Economy as a Science of Government,” in Geenens and Rosenblatt, French Liberalism, 192–207.

85 Serge Audier, “Is There a French Neoliberalism?”, in Geenens and Rosenblatt, French Liberalism, 208–29. See, too, Audier's, Néo-libéralisme(s). Une archéologie intellectuelle (Paris, 2012)Google Scholar.

86 Richard Whatmore, “War, Trade and Empire: The Dilemmas of French Political Economy, 1780–1816,” in Geenens and Rosenblatt, French Liberalism, 169–91. See, too, Whatmore's, Republicanism and the French Revolution: An Intellectual History of Jean-Baptiste Say's Political Economy (Oxford, 2001)Google Scholar.

87 On this topic see Boudon, Raymond's provocative study, Pourquoi les intellectuels n’aiment pas le libéralisme (Paris, 2004)Google Scholar.

88 Céline Spector, “Was Montesquieu Liberal? The Spirit of Laws in the History of Liberalism,” in Geenens and Rosenblatt, French Liberalism, 57–72, at 65; Rosenblatt, “On the Need for a Protestant Reformation,” 122, Rosenblatt’s emphasis.

89 Jaume, Lucien, Tocqueville: Les sources aristocratiques de la liberté (Paris, 2008), especially Part ThreeGoogle Scholar.

90 Hunt, Lynn, Inventing Human Rights: A History (New York, 2007)Google Scholar.

91 Zeldin, Theodore, A History of French Passions, 5 vols. (Oxford, 1973–7)Google Scholar.

92 Reddy, William M., The Navigation of Feeling: A Framework for the History of Emotions (Cambridge, 2001)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

93 Nussbaum, Martha C., Political Emotions: Why Love Matters for Justice (Cambridge and London, 2013), 4Google Scholar.