Hostname: page-component-76fb5796d-qxdb6 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-29T11:18:00.542Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Discoverers' Induction

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 April 2022

Laura J. Snyder*
Affiliation:
Department of Philosophy, St. John's University
*
Send reprint requests to the author, Department of Philosophy, St. John's University, 8000 Utopia Parkway, Jamaica, NY 11439.

Abstract

In this paper I demonstrate that, contrary to the standard interpretations, William Whewell's view of scientific method is neither that of the hypothetico-deductivist nor that of the retroductivist. Rather, he offers a unique inductive methodology, which he calls “discoverers' induction.” After explicating this methodology, I show that Kepler's discovery of his first law of planetary motion conforms to it, as Whewell claims it does. In explaining Whewell's famous phrase about “happy guesses” in science, I suggest that Whewell intended a distinction between “inductions,” which can be empirically verified, and “mere hypotheses”—or guesses—which cannot. Finally, I argue that Whewell's discoverers' induction is a view worthy of our attention today, because it avoids a number of problems faced by prominent alternative methodologies.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © Philosophy of Science Association 1997

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

Several of the points made here were initially presented at the Philosophy of Science Association/History of Science Society joint meetings in October, 1994, as part of the session entitled “William Whewell (1794–1866): The Bicentennial Session.” I received helpful comments from audience members, especially Ernan McMullin and Geoffrey Cantor, as well as from the other participants in the session: Harvey Becher, Michael Ruse, and David Wilson. Earlier versions of this paper were read by Peter Achinstein, Stephen Barker, Arthur Gianelli, Kenneth Schaffner, and Robert Smith; I appreciate their suggestions, as well as those of an anonymous referee of this journal.

References

Achinstein, P. (1985), “The Method of Hypothesis: What is it Supposed to do, and Can it do it?”, in Achinstein, P. and Hannaway, O. (eds.), Observation, Experiment and Hypotheses in Modern Physical Sciences. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, pp. 126145.Google Scholar
Achinstein, P. (1991), Particles and Waves. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Brown, J.R. and Mittelstrass, J. (eds.) (1989), An Intimate Relation. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Buchdahl, G. (1991), “Deductivist versus Inductivist Approaches in the Philosophy of Science as Illustrated by Some Controversies Between Whewell and Mill”, in Fisch and Schaffer 1991, pp. 311344.Google Scholar
Butts, R. (1977), “Consilience of Inductions and the Problem of Conceptual Change in Science”, in Colodny, Robert G. (ed.), Logic, Laws and Life: Some Philosophical Complications. Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press, pp. 7188.Google Scholar
Butts, R. (1987), “Pragmatism in Theories of Induction in the Victorian Era: Herschel, Whewell, Mach and Mill”, in Stachowiak, Herbert (ed.), Pragmatik: Handbuch Pragmatischen Denkens (Band II, Der Aufstieg Pragmatischen Denkens im 19. und 20. Jahrhundert). Hamburg: F. Meiner, pp. 4058.Google Scholar
Curd, M. (1980), “The Logic of Discovery: An Analysis of Three Approaches”, in Nickles 1980, pp. 201220.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
DeMorgan, A. (1859), “Review of Whewell's Novum Organum [sic] Renovatum”, The Athenaeum, no. 1628, pp. 4244.Google Scholar
Donahue, W. (1988), “Kepler's Fabricated Figures: Covering up the Mess in the New Astronomy”, New Astronomy 19: 217237.Google Scholar
Donahue, W. (1992), “Translator's Introduction”, in Kepler 1609/1992, pp. 119.Google Scholar
Douglas, Mrs. S. (1881), The Life and Selections from the Correspondence of William Whewell, D.D. London: C. Kegan Paul and Co.Google Scholar
Earman, J. (1985), “Concepts of Projectibility and Problems of Induction”, Noûs 19:521–535.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Feynman, R. (1965), The Character of Physical Law. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Fisch, M. (1985), “Whewell's Consilience of Inductions: An Evaluation”, Philosophy of Science 52: 239255.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fisch, M. (1991), William Whewell, Philosopher of Science. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Fisch, M. and Schaffer, S. (eds.) (1991), William Whewell: A Composite Portrait. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Forster, M.R. (1988), “Unification, Explanation, and the Composition of Causes in Newtonian Mechanics”, Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 19: 55101.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gemes, K. (1993), “Hypothetico-deductivism, Content, and the Natural Axiomatization of Theories”, Philosophy of Science 60: 477487.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Grimes, T. R. (1990), “Discussion: Truth, Content, and the Hypothetico-deductive Method”, Philosophy of Science 57: 514522.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hanson, N.R. (1958), Patterns of Discovery: An Inquiry into the Conceptual Foundations of Science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Harper, W. (1989), “Consilience and Natural Kind Reasoning”, in Brown and Mittelstrass 1989, pp. 115152.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hempel, C.G. (1966), Philosophy of Natural Science. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.Google Scholar
Herschel, J.F.W. (1830), Preliminary Discourse on the Study of Natural Philosophy. Facsimile of the original edition, with a foreword by Arthur Fine (1987). Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Hesse, M.B. (1971), “Whewell's Consilience of Inductions and Predictions [Reply to Laudan]”, Monist 55: 520524.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kepler, J. (1609), New Astronomy. Translated by William H. Donahue (1992). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Kleiner, S. (1983), “A New Look at Kepler and Abductive Argument”, Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 14: 279313.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Koestler, A. (1960), The Watershed: A Biography of Johannes Kepler. Garden City, NY: Academic Press of America.Google Scholar
Kozhamthadam, J. (1994), The Discovery of Kepler's Laws: The Interaction of Science, Philosophy, and Religion. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press.Google Scholar
Laudari, L. (1971), “William Whewell on the Consilience oflnductions”, Monist 55: 368391.Google Scholar
Laudari, L. (1981), Science and Hypothesis. Dordrecht: Reidel.Google Scholar
Lugg, A. (1985), “The Process of Discovery”, Philosophy of Science 52: 207220.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lugg, A. (1989), “History, Discovery and Induction: Whewell on Kepler on the Orbit of Mars”, in Brown and Mittelstrass 1989, pp. 283298.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mandelbaum, M. (1964), “Newton and Boyle and the Problem of ‘Transdiction’”, in his Philosophy, Science and Sense Perception. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, pp. 61117.Google Scholar
Mill, J.S. (1872), A System of Logic Rationative and Inductive, 8th edition. Edited by J.M. Robson, with an introduction by R.F. McRae. Collected Works of John Stuart Mill, volumes VII and VIII (1973). Toronto: University of Toronto Press.Google Scholar
Newton, I. (1687), Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy and The System of the World. Translated by Andrew Motte, revised and edited by Florian Cajori (1962). Berkeley: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Lugg, A. (1960) The Correspondence of Isaac Newton, vol. 2. Turnbull, H.W. (ed.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Nickles, T. (ed.) (1980), Scientific Discovery, Logic and Rationality. Dordrecht: Reidel.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nickles, T. (ed.) (1985), “Beyond Divorce: Current Status of the Discovery Debate”, Philosophy of Science 52:177–206.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Niiniluoto, I. (1977), “Notes on Popper as a Follower of Whewell and Peirce”, Ajatus 37: 272327.Google Scholar
Peirce, C. (1865),“Lecture on the Theories of Whewell, Mill, and Comte”, in Max H. Fisch (ed.) (1982), Writings of Charles S. Peirce: A Chronological Edition, vol. 1. Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press, pp. 205223.Google Scholar
Peirce, C. (1958–1960), Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (eds.), vol. 1–6 (1960); Arthur W. Burks (ed.), vol. 7–8 (1958). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Ross, S. (1962), “‘Scientist’: The Story of a Word”, Annals of Science 18: 6585.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ruse, M. (1975), “Darwin's Debt to Philosophy: An Examination of the Influence of the Philosophical Ideas of John F.W. Herschel and William Whewell on the Development of Charles Darwin's Theory of Evolution”, Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 6: 159181.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Snyder, L.J. (1994), “It's All Necessarily So: William Whewell on Scientific Truth”, Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 25: 785807.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Snyder, L.J. (1997), “The Mill-Whewell Debate: Much Ado about Induction”, Perspectives on Science 5:159–198.Google Scholar
Stephenson, B. (1987), Kepler's Physical Astronomy. Princeton: Princeton University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stoll, M.R. (1929), Whewell's Philosophy of Induction. Lancaster, PA: Lancaster Press.Google Scholar
Todhunter, I. (1876), William Whewell, D.D., An Account of his Writings, with Selections from his Literary and Scientific Correspondence, in two volumes. London: Macmillan and Co.Google Scholar
Venn, J. (1889), The Principles of Empirical or Inductive Logic, 2nd edition (1907). London: Macmillan and Co.Google Scholar
Waters, C.K. (1987), “Relevance Logic Brings Hope to Hypothetico-deductivism”, Philosophy of Science 54: 453464.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wettersten, J. (1994), “Discussion: William Whewell: Problems of Induction vs. Problems of Rationality”, British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 45: 716742.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Whewell, W. (1831), “Review of J. Herschel's Preliminary Discourse on the Study of Natural Philosophy (1830)”, Quarterly Review 45: 374407.Google Scholar
Whewell, W. (1834), “Mrs. Somerville on the Connection of the Sciences”, Quarterly Review 51: 5468.Google Scholar
Whewell, W. (1838), “Remarks on Mathematical Reasoning and on the Logic of Induction”, appended to The Mechanical Euclid, 3rd edition. Cambridge: J. and J.J. Deighton, and London: John W. Parker.Google Scholar
Whewell, W. (1847), The Philosophy of the Inductive Sciences, Founded Upon Their History, 2nd edition, in two volumes. London: John W. Parker. Facsimile (minus the Inductive Tables) published with an introduction by John Herivel (1967). New York and London: Johnson Reprint Corp.Google Scholar
Whewell, W. (1849), Of Induction, with especial reference to Mr. J. Stuart Mill's System of Logic. London: John W. Parker.Google Scholar
Whewell, W. (1857), The History of the Inductive Sciences, from the Earliest to the Present Time, 3rd edition with additions, in two volumes. London: John W. Parker. Reprinted (1873). New York: D. Appleton and Co.Google Scholar
Whewell, W. (1858a), Novum Organon Renovatum. London: John W. Parker.Google Scholar
Whewell, W. (1858b), The History of Scientific Ideas, in two volumes. London: John W. Parker.Google Scholar
Whewell, W. (1860), On the Philosophy of Discovery: Chapters Historical and Critical. London: John W. Parker. Facsimile edition (1971). New York: Burt Franklin.Google Scholar
Yeo, R. (1993), Defining Science: William Whewell, Natural Knowledge, and Public Debate in Early Victorian Britain. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar