Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-5nwft Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-05-18T00:58:51.360Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The Evolutionary Roots of Moral Responsibility

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  27 March 2023

Marcelo Fischborn*
Affiliation:
Farroupilha Federal Institute of Education, Science, and Technology, Uruguaiana, RS, Brazil.

Abstract

Judging a person as morally responsible involves believing that certain responses (such as punishment, reward, or expressions of blame or praise) can be justifiably directed at the person. This paper develops an account of the evolution of moral responsibility judgment that adopts Michael Tomasello’s two-step theory of the evolution of morality and borrows also from Christopher Boehm’s work. The main hypothesis defended is that moral responsibility judgment originally evolved as an adaptation that enabled groups of cooperative individuals to hold free riders responsible more safely by acting in a coordinated way.

Type
Article
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2023. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of the Philosophy of Science Association

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Anscombe, G. E. M. 1957. Intention. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.Google Scholar
Apicella, Coren L., and Silk, Joan B.. 2019. “The Evolution of Human Cooperation.” Current Biology 29 (11): R44750. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.cub.2019.03.036.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Aquino, Karl, Tripp, Thomas M., and Bies, Robert J.. 2001. “How Employees Respond to Personal Offense: The Effects of Blame Attribution, Victim Status, and Offender Status on Revenge and Reconciliation in the Workplace.” Journal of Applied Psychology 86 (1): 5259. https://doi.org/10.1037/0021-9010.86.1.52.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Aristotle. 2004. Nichomachean Ethics. Translated by Crisp, Roger. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Balliet, Daniel, Mulder, Laetitia B., and Van Lange, Paul A. M.. 2011. “Reward, Punishment, and Cooperation: A Meta-Analysis.” Psychological Bulletin 137 (4): 594615. https://doi.org/10.1037/a0023489.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Boehm, Christopher. 2012. Moral Origins: The Evolution of Virtue, Altruism, and Shame. New York: Basic Books.Google Scholar
Boyd, Robert, and Richerson, Peter J.. 1992. “Punishment Allows the Evolution of Cooperation (or Anything Else) in Sizable Groups.” Ethology and Sociobiology 13 (3): 171–95. https://doi.org/10.1016/0162-3095(92)90032-Y.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Caruso, Gregg D., and Pereboom, Derk. 2020. “A Non-Punitive Alternative to Retributive Punishment.” In Routledge Handbook of the Philosophy and Science of Punishment, edited by Focquaert, Farah, Waller, Bruce, and Shaw, Elizabeth, 355–65. Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Clark, Cory J., Luguri, Jamie B., Ditto, Peter H., Knobe, Joshua, Shariff, Azim F., and Baumeister, Roy F.. 2014. “Free to Punish: A Motivated Account of Free Will Belief.” Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 106 (4): 501–13. https://doi.org/10.1037/a0035880.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Clark, Cory J., Winegard, B. M., and Shariff, A. F.. 2021. “Motivated Free Will Belief: The Theory, New (Preregistered) Studies, and Three Meta-Analyses.” Journal of Experimental Psychology. General 150 (7): e2247. https://doi.org/10.1037/xge0000993.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cova, Florian, Brent Strickland, Angela Abatista, Aurélien Allard, James Andow, Mario Attie, James Beebe, et al. 2018. “Estimating the Reproducibility of Experimental Philosophy.” Review of Philosophy and Psychology, June. https://doi.org/10.1007/s13164-018-0400-9.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fischborn, Marcelo. 2018. “How Should Free Will Skeptics Pursue Legal Change?Neuroethics 11 (1): 4754. https://doi.org/10.1007/s12152-017-9333-8.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gonzalez, Miriam, Ateah, Christine A., Durrant, Joan E., and Feldgaier, Steven. 2019. “The Impact of the Triple P Seminar Series on Canadian Parents’ Use of Physical Punishment, Non-Physical Punishment and Non-Punitive Responses.” Behaviour Change 36 (2): 102–20. https://doi.org/10.1017/bec.2019.7.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hamlin, J. K., Wynn, K., Bloom, P., and Mahajan, N.. 2011. “How Infants and Toddlers React to Antisocial Others.” Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences 108 (50): 19931–36. https://doi.org/10.1073/pnas.1110306108.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Henrich, Joseph, and Boyd, Robert. 2001. “Why People Punish Defectors.” Journal of Theoretical Biology 208 (1): 7989. https://doi.org/10.1006/jtbi.2000.2202.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Hoffman, Morris B., and Krueger, Frank. 2017. “The Neuroscience of Blame and Punishment.” In Self, Culture and Consciousness, edited by Menon, Sangeetha, Nagaraj, Nithin, and Binoy, V. V., 207–23. Singapore: Springer Singapore. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-981-10-5777-9_13.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Knobe, Joshua. 2003. “Intentional Action and Side Effects in Ordinary Language.” Analysis 63 (279): 190–94. https://doi.org/10.1111/1467-8284.00419.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Laforest, Marty. 2002. “Scenes of Family Life: Complaining in Everyday Conversation.” Journal of Pragmatics 34: 1595–620. https://doi.org/10.1016/S0378-2166(02)00077-2.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Machery, Edouard, and Mallon, Ron. 2010. “Evolution of Morality.” In The Moral Psychology Handbook, edited by Doris, John Michael, 346. Oxford: Oxford University Press. CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Malle, Bertram F., Guglielmo, Steve, and Monroe, Andrew E.. 2014. “A Theory of Blame.” Psychological Inquiry 25: 147–86. https://doi.org/10.1080/1047840X.2014.877340.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mameli, Matteo. 2013. “Meat Made Us Moral: A Hypothesis on the Nature and Evolution of Moral Judgment.” Biology & Philosophy 28 (6): 903–31. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-013-9401-3.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McDonald, Melissa, Roni Porat, Ayala Yarkoney, Michal Reifen Tagar, Sasha Kimel, Saguy, Tamar, and Halperin, Eran. 2017. “Intergroup Emotional Similarity Reduces Dehumanization and Promotes Conciliatory Attitudes in Prolonged Conflict.” Group Processes & Intergroup Relations 20 (1): 125–36. https://doi.org/10.1177/1368430215595107.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Michael, John Andrew, and Szigeti, András. 2019. “‘The Group Knobe Effect’: Evidence That People Intuitively Attribute Agency and Responsibility to Groups.” Philosophical Explorations 22 (1): 4461. https://doi.org/10.1080/13869795.2018.1492007.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Monroe, Andrew E., Brady, Garrett, and Malle, Bertram F.. 2017. “This Isn’t the Free Will Worth Looking for: General Free Will Beliefs Do Not Influence Moral Judgments; Agent-Specific Choice Ascriptions Do.” Social Psychological and Personality Science 8 (2): 191–99. https://doi.org/10.1177/1948550616667616.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Monroe, Andrew E., and Ysidron, Dominic W.. 2021. “Not so Motivated after All? Three Replication Attempts and a Theoretical Challenge to a Morally Motivated Belief in Free Will.” Journal of Experimental Psychology. General 150 (1): e112. https://doi.org/10.1037/xge0000788.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Morris, Norval, and Rothman, David J.. 1995. “Introduction.” In The Oxford History of the Prison, edited by Morris, Norval and David, J. Rothman, viixiv. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Nadelhoffer, Thomas. 2006. “Bad Acts, Blameworthy Agents, and Intentional Actions: Some Problems for Juror Impartiality.” Philosophical Explorations 9 (2): 203–19. https://doi.org/10.1080/13869790600641905.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Raihani, Nichola J., and Bshary, Redouan. 2019. “Punishment: One Tool, Many Uses.” Evolutionary Human Sciences 1: e12. https://doi.org/10.1017/ehs.2019.12.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schooler, Jonathan, Nadelhoffer, Thomas, Nahmias, Eddy, and Vohs, Kathleen D.. 2015. “Measuring and Manipulating Beliefs and Behaviors Associated with Free Will: The Good, the Bad, and the Ugly.” In Surrounding Freedom: Philosophy, Psychology, Neuroscience, edited by Alfred, R. Mele, 7294. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Strawson, Peter F. 1962. “Freedom and Resentment.” In Free Will, edited by Pereboom, Derk, 148–71. Indianapolis: Hackett.Google Scholar
Svennevig, Jan. 2012. “On Being Heard in Emergency Calls. The Development of Hostility in a Fatal Emergency Call.” Journal of Pragmatics 44 (11): 1393–412. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.pragma.2012.06.001.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Talbert, Matthew. 2019. “Moral Responsibility.” In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, edited by Edward, N. Zalta. Stanford: Stanford University Press. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2019/entries/moral-responsibility/.Google Scholar
Tomasello, Michael. 2016. A Natural History of Human Morality. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tomasello, Michael, Melis, Alicia P., Tennie, Claudio, Wyman, Emily, and Herrmann, Esther. 2012. “Two Key Steps in the Evolution of Human Cooperation: The Interdependence Hypothesis.” Current Anthropology 53 (6): 673–92. https://doi.org/10.1086/668207.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wallace, R. Jay. 1996. Responsibility and the Moral Sentiments. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Waller, Bruce N. 2015. The Stubborn System of Moral Responsibility. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press. https://doi.org/10.7551/mitpress/9780262028165.001.0001.Google Scholar
Zimmerman, Michael. 2015. “Varieties of Moral Responsibility.” In The Nature of Moral Responsibility: New Essays, edited by Clarke, Randolph, McKenna, Michael, and Angela, M. Smith, 4564. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar