Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-ndmmz Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-06-13T08:25:38.488Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The Imagery Debate

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 April 2022

Kim Sterelny*
Affiliation:
Department of Philosophy, University of Maryland, College Park

Abstract

One central debate in cognitive science is over imagery. Do images constitute, or constitute evidence for, a distinctive, depictive form of mental representation? The most sophisticated advocacy of this view has been developed by Kosslyn and his coworkers. This paper focuses on his position and argues (i) that though Kosslyn has not developed a satisfactory account of depiction, there is nothing in principle unintelligible about the idea of depictive neural representation, but (ii) Kosslyn's model of imagery rescues the intelligibility of pictorialism at the cost of its explanatory power.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © The Philosophy of Science Association 1986

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

Thanks to David Armstrong, Ned Block, Michael Devitt, and Bill Lycan for their comments on earlier versions of this paper.

References

Block, N. (ed.) (1981), Imagery. Cambridge and London: The MIT Press.Google Scholar
Block, N. (ed.) (1983a), “The Photographic Fallacy in the Debate about Mental Imagery”, Noûs 17: 651–62.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Block, N. (ed.) (1983b), “Mental Pictures and Cognitive Science”, Philosophical Review 92: 499541CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brown, R., and Herrnstein, R. J. (1981), “Icons and Images”, in Block (1981), pp. 1949.Google Scholar
Dennett, D. C. (1978), Brainstorms. Cambridge: The MIT Press/A Bradford Book.Google Scholar
Dennett, D. C. (1981), “Three Kinds of Intentional Psychology”, in Reduction, Time and Reality. Healey, R., (ed.). New York and London: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Dretske, F. (1978), “The Role of the Percept in Visual Cognition”, in Perception and Cognition, Savage, C. W. (ed.). Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
Fodor, J. A. (1975), The Language of Thought, London: Thomas Y. Crowell.Google Scholar
Fodor, J. A. (1978), “Prepositional Attitudes”, The Monist 61: 501–23.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fodor, J. A. (1980), “Methodological Solipsism Considered as a Research Strategy for Cognitive Psychology”, The Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3: 63110.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goodman, N. (1968), Languages of Art. New York: Bobbs-Merrill.Google Scholar
Haugeland, J. (1981), a Analog and analog“, Philosophical Topics 12: 213–26.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kosslyn, S. M. (1980), Image and Mind. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Kosslyn, S. M. (1981), “The Medium and the Message in Mental Imagery; A Theory”, in Block (1981), 207–44.Google Scholar
Kosslyn, S. M.; Pinker, S.; Smith, G. E.; and Schwartz, S. P. (1979), “On the Demystification of Mental Imagery”, The Behavioural and Brain Sciences 2: 535–81.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kosslyn, S. M., and Pomerantz, J. R. (1978), “Imagery, Propositions and the Form of Internal Representations”, in Readings in Philosophy of Psychology, Vol. 2. Block, N. (ed.). Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Lycan, W. G. (1981), “Towards a Homuncular Theory of Believing”, Cognition and Brain Theory 4.Google Scholar
Palmer, S. E. (1978), “Fundamental Aspects of Cognitive Representation”, Cognition and Categorization, Rosch, E. and Lloyd, B. B. (eds.). Hillsdale NJ: Erlbaum Associates.Google Scholar
Pylyshyn, Z. W. (1973), “What the Mind's Eye Tells the Mind's Brain”, Psychological Bulletin 80: 124.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pylyshyn, Z. W. (1978), “Imagery and Artificial Intelligence”, in Perception and Cognition, Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, Vol. 9. Savage, C. Wade (ed.). Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
Pylyshyn, Z. W. (1980), “Computation and Cognition”, The Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3: 111–69.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pylyshyn, Z. W. (1981), “The Imagery Debate: Analog Media versus Tacit Knowledge”, in Block (1981), pp. 151206.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rey, G. (1981), “What are Mental Images?” in Readings in the Philosophy of Psychology, Vol. 2. Block, N. (ed.). Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Richman, C. L.; Mitchell, D. B.; and Reznick, S. (1979), “The Demands of Mental Travel”, Behavioral and Brain Sciences 2: 564–65.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sterelny, K. (1981), Critical Notice of D.C. Dennett's Brainstorms, Australasian Journal of Philosophy 58: 442–53.Google Scholar
Sterelny, K. (1983), “Mental Representation: What Language is Brainese?”, Philosophical Studies 43: 365–82.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sterelny, K. (1984), Critical Notice of A. Woodfield (ed.), Thought and Object, Journal of Semantics 3.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shepard, Roger N. (1975), “Form, Formation and Transformation of Internal Representations”, in Information Processes and Cognition, R. L. Solso (ed.)., The Loyola Symposium. Washington DC: V.H. Winston.Google Scholar