Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-75dct Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-06-11T20:04:51.089Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The “Structure” of the “Strategy”: Looking at the Matthewson-Weisberg Trade-off and Its Justificatory Role for the Multiple-Models Approach

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2022

Abstract

The multiple-models approach, which has its origins in Levins’s work, is gaining broader acceptance among philosophers. Levins asserted that there is a trade-off between modeling desiderata, which justified the multiple-models approach through two separate justificatory paths. Some attention has been paid to the trade-off thesis, culminating in a paper by Matthewson and Weisberg. However, no attention has been paid to how the trade-off is supposed to justify the multiple-models approach. I argue that a trade-off between generality and precision cannot support one of Levins’s justificatory paths, and I consider what that might mean for the multiple-models approach.

Type
General Philosophy of Science
Copyright
Copyright © The Philosophy of Science Association

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

I thank Elliott Sober, Malcolm Forster, Dan Hausman, Jay Odenbaugh, James Justus, John Basl, Matthew Kopec, Hayley Clatterbuck, Roberta Millstein, John Matthewson, Trevor Pearce, Roman Frigg, and Michael Weisberg for their helpful comments and advice.

References

Da Costa, Newton, and French, Steven. 2003. Science and Partial Truth. Oxford: Oxford University Press.10.1093/019515651X.001.0001CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Forster, Malcolm. 2000. “Key Concepts in Models Selection: Performance and Generalizability.” Journal of Mathematical Psychology 44:205–31.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Forster, Malcolm 2001. “The New Science of Simplicity.” In Simplicity, Inference, and Modelling, ed. Zellner, Arnold, Keuzenkamp, H. A., and McAleer, Michael, 83119. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Forster, Malcolm, and Sober, Elliott. 1994. “How to Tell When Simpler, More Unified, or Less Ad Hoc Theories Will Provide More Accurate Predictions.” British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 45:135.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Freidman, Michael. 1974. “Explanation and Scientific Understanding.” Journal of Philosophy 71 (1): 519..CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Giere, Ronald. 1988. Explaining Science: A Cognitive Approach. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Godfrey-Smith, Peter. 2006. “The Strategy of Model Based Science.” Biology and Philosophy 21:625–40.Google Scholar
Hempel, Carl. 1965. Aspects of Scientific Explanation. New York: Free Press.Google Scholar
Hitchcock, Christopher, and Woodward, James. 2003. “Explanatory Generalizations.” Pt. 2, “Plumbing Explanatory Depth.” Noûs 37 (2): 181–99..CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kitcher, Philip. 1989. “Explanatory Unification and the Causal Structure of the World.” In Scientific Explanation, ed. Kitcher, Philip and Salmon, Wesley, 410505. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
Levins, Richard. 1966. “The Strategy of Model Building in Population Biology.” American Scientist 54:421–31.Google Scholar
Matthewson, John, and Weisberg, Michael. 2009. “The Structure of Tradeoffs in Model Building.” Synthese 170 (1): 169–90..10.1007/s11229-008-9366-yCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Orzack, Steven H., and Sober, Elliott. 1993. “A Critical Assessment of Levins’s ‘The Strategy of Model Building in Population Biology (1966).’Quarterly Review of Biology 68:533–46.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sober, Elliott. 1999. “The Multiple Realizability Argument against Reductionism.” Philosophy of Science 66:542–64.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sober, Elliott 2008. Evidence and Evolution. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Strevens, Michael. 2009. Depth: An Account of Scientific Explanation. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Suppes, Patrick. 2002. Representation and Invariance of Scientific Structures. Stanford, CA: CSLI Publications.Google Scholar
van Fraassen, Bas. 1980. The Scientific Image. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Weisberg, Michael. 2006. “Forty Years of ‘The Strategy’: Levins on Model Building and Idealization.” Biology and Philosophy 21 (5): 623–45..Google Scholar
Weisberg, Michael 2007a. “Three Kinds of Idealization.” Journal of Philosophy 104 (12): 639–59..10.5840/jphil20071041240CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Weisberg, Michael 2007b. “Who Is a Modeler?British Journal for Philosophy of Science 58:207–33.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wimsatt, William. 1980. “Randomness and Perceived Randomness in Evolutionary Biology.” Synthese 43:287329.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wimsatt, William 1987. “False Models as Means to Truer Theories.” In Neutral Models in Biology, ed. Nitecki, Matthew and Hoffman, Antoni, 2355. London: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Woodward, James. 2003. Making Things Happen: A Theory of Causal Explanation. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar