Hostname: page-component-76fb5796d-skm99 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-28T06:23:13.089Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Religious and Secular Statements

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  25 February 2009

D. H. Mellor
Affiliation:
Faculty of Philosophy, University of Cambridge

Extract

The relation between religious and scientific explanations of events and states of affairs has been the subject of much debate. For example, are the statements

‘John's life was saved by surgery’

‘John's life was saved in answer to prayer’

in competition with each other and, if so, in what way? They do not seem to be rival causal explanations, nor are they straightforwardly contradictory. Yet each seems to cast doubt on the other, or at least to make it to some extent redundant.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © The Royal Institute of Philosophy 1974

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Alexander, P. (1956) Complementary descriptions Mind, 65, 145165.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Duhem, P. (1914) The Aim and Structure of Physical Theory. Trans. Wiener, P. P. (1954). Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Eddington, A. S. (1928) The Nature of the Physical World. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Einstein, A. (1923) Geometry and experience. Readings in the Philosophy of Science (ed. Feigl, H. and Brodbeck, M. (1953)), pp. 189194. New York: Appleton-Century-Crofts.Google Scholar
Feyerabend, P. K. (1962) Explanation, reduction and empiricism. Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, Vol. 3. (ed. Feigl, H. and Maxwell, G.), pp. 2897. Minnesota University Press.Google Scholar
Feyerabend, P. K. (1966) The structure of science. Br. J. Phil. Sci., 17, 237249.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Grünbaum, A. (1964) Philosophical Problems of Space and Time. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Kuhn, T. S. (1962) The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. Chicago University Press.Google Scholar
Mackay, D. M. (1958) Complementarity. Arist. Soc., Suppl. Vol. 32, 105122.Google Scholar
Maxwell, G. (1962) The ontological status of theoretical entities. Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, Vol. 3 (ed. Feigl, H. and Maxwell, G.), pp. 327. Minnesota University Press.Google Scholar
Mellor, D. H. (1969) Physics and furniture. Am. Phil. Q. Monograph No. 3 (ed. N. Rescher), pp. 171187.Google Scholar
Moore, Dom S. (1967) God is a New Language. London: Darton Longman and Todd.Google Scholar
Nagel, E. (1961) The Structure of Science. New York: Harcourt, Brace and World.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Quine, W. V. O. (1952) Methods of Logic. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Quine, W. V. O. (1953) From a Logical Point of View. Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Russell, B. (1919) Introduction to Mathematical Philosophy. London: Allen and Unwin.Google Scholar
Ryle, G. (1954) Dilemmas. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Sellars, W. (1961) The language of theories. Current Issues in the Philosophy of Science (ed. Feigl, H. and Maxwell, G.), pp. 5777. New York: Holt, Rinehart and Wilson.Google Scholar
Stebbing, L. S. (1937) Philosophy and the Physicists. London: Methuen.Google Scholar
Strawson, P. F. (1952) Introduction to Logical Theory. London: Methuen.Google Scholar