Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-dsjbd Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-09T04:14:34.675Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Self-Knowledge and Hume's Phenomenology of the Passions

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  28 May 2021

Abstract

Taxonomies of the passions have long claimed to serve a quest for self-knowledge, by specifying conditions under which certain passions arise, formal objects they possess, and qualities essential to their particular feelings. I argue that David Hume's theory of the passions provides resources for a different kind of self-knowledge – a sceptical self-knowledge depending on our ability to articulate how the passions feel rather than always identifying our passions as tokens of an identifiable passion-type. These resources are distinctions between four qualitative aspects that passions may possess – pleasantness or painfulness, calmness or violence, invigoration or softening, and directedness or lack thereof towards specific actions. Reflection on these aspects produces a more accurate understanding of the nature of our emotions and chastens our judgmental tendencies in ways that benefit both self and others.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © The Royal Institute of Philosophy 2021

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Aquinas, Thomas, Summa Theologiae, (New Advent, Accessed 11 April 2020), http://www.newadvent.org/summa/.Google Scholar
Aristotle, The Complete Works of Aristotle, Barnes, Jonathan, ed. (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1984).Google Scholar
Baier, Annette, ‘Hume on Resentment’, Hume Studies 6 (1980), 133–49.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Baldwin, James, ‘Stranger in the Village’, in Morrison, Toni, ed., Collected Essays (New York: Library of America, 1998).Google Scholar
Barrett, Lisa Feldman, ‘Are Emotions Natural Kinds?Perspectives on Psychological Science 1 (2006), 2858.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Charland, Louis C., ‘The Natural Kind Status of Emotion’, The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 53 (2002), 511–37.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cicero, Marcus Tullius, Cicero on the Emotions, Graver, Margaret, trans. (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2002).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Eliot, George, Middlemarch, (London: Penguin, 2003).Google Scholar
Fieser, James, ‘Hume's Classification of the Passions and Its Precursors’, Hume Studies 18 (1992), 117.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Don Garrett, Don, Cognition and Commitment in Hume's Philosophy (New York: Oxford University Press, 1997).Google Scholar
Goldie, Peter, ‘Emotions, Feelings, and Intentionality’, Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 1 (2002), 235–54.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Griffiths, Paul E., ‘Is Emotion a Natural Kind?’, in Solomon, Robert C., ed., Thinking About Feeling: Contemporary Philosophers on Emotion (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2004).Google Scholar
Hume, David, Essays: Moral, Political, and Literary, Miller, Eugene F., ed. (Indianapolis: Liberty Fund, 1985).Google Scholar
Hume, David, An Enquiry concerning the Principles of Morals, Beauchamp, Tom L., ed. (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1998).Google Scholar
Hume, David, A Dissertation on the Passions, The Natural History of Religion, Beauchamp, Tom L., ed. (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2007).Google Scholar
Hume, David, A Treatise of Human Nature, Norton, David Fate and Norton, Mary J., eds. (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2011).Google Scholar
Lazarus, Richard S., ‘Progress on a Cognitive-Motivational-relational Theory of Emotion’, American Psychologist 46 (1991), 819–34.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Maugham, W. Somerset, The Moon and Sixpence (New York: Penguin, 1944).Google Scholar
McIntyre, Jane L., ‘Hume's Passions: Direct and Indirect’, Hume Studies 26 (2000), 7786.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Qu, Hsueh, ‘The Simple Duality: Humean Passions’, Canadian Journal of Philosophy 42 (2012), 98116.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Qu, Hsueh, ‘Hume on Mental Transparency’, Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 98 (2017), 576601.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Qu, Hsueh, 'Hume's (Ad Hoc?) Appeal to the Calm Passions', Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 100 (2018), 444–69.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Radcliffe, Elizabeth S., Hume, Passion, and Action (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2018).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Scarantino, Andrea, ‘How to Define Emotions Scientifically’, Emotion Review 4 (2012), 358–68.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schmicking, Daniel A., ‘Hume's Theory of Simple Impressions Reconsidered’, Hume Studies 30 (2004), 133.Google Scholar
Solomon, Robert C., True to Our Feelings (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2007).Google Scholar
Taylor, Jacqueline A., Reflecting Subjects: Passion, Sympathy, and Society in Hume's Philosophy (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2015).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Watkins, Margaret, ‘Delicate Magnanimity: Hume on the Advantages of Taste’, History of Philosophy Quarterly 26 (2009), 389408.Google Scholar
Watkins, Margaret, The Philosophical Progress of Hume's Essays (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2019a).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Watkins, Margaret, ‘Unprincipled by Principle: On Hume's Use of Affection’, in Ruys, Juanita Feros, Champion, Michael, and Essary, Kirk, eds., Before Emotion: The Language of Feeling (400–1800) (Routledge, 2019b).Google Scholar
Watkins, Margaret, ‘Virtues Suspect and Sublime’, in Kroeker, Esther Engels and Lemmens, Willem, eds., Hume's An Enquiry Concerning the Principles of Morals: A Critical Guide (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2021).Google Scholar
Williams, Lisa A., ‘Emotions of Excellence: Communal and Agentic Functions of Pride, Moral Elevation, and Admiration,’ in Lench, Heather C., ed., The Function of Emotions (Cham: Springer International Publishing, 2018).Google Scholar
Woolf, Virginia, ‘Montaigne’, in The Common Reader, 5969 (New York: Harcourt, Brace & World, 1925).Google Scholar