Hostname: page-component-8448b6f56d-jr42d Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-19T13:58:53.043Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Making Sense of Self-Deception: Distinguishing Self-Deception from Delusion, Moral Licensing, Cognitive Dissonance and Other Self-Distortions*

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  18 September 2017

Abstract

There has been no systematic study in the literature of how self-deception differs from other kinds of self-distortion. For example, the term ‘cognitive dissonance’ has been used in some cases as a rag-bag term for all kinds of self-distortion. To address this, a narrow definition is given: self-deception involves injecting a given set of facts with an erroneous fact to make an ex ante suboptimal decision seem as if it were ex ante optimal. Given this narrow definition, this paper delineates self-deception from deception as well as from other kinds of self-distortions such as delusion, moral licensing, cognitive dissonance, manipulation, and introspective illusion.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © The Royal Institute of Philosophy 2017 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

*

This paper benefited from the comments of Robert Trivers, William von Hippel, Gerd Gigerenzer, Robin E. Pope, Richard Posner, Haiou Zhou, Jonathan Baron, Philip T. Dunwoody, Andreas Ortmann, Steven Gardner, Athena Aktipis, and anonymous referees. It also benefited from the research assistance of Michael Dunstan and Peter Lambert. The usual caveat applies.

References

1 Caldwell, C., ‘Identity, Self-Awareness, and Self-Deception: Ethical Implications for Leaders and Organizations’, Journal of Business Ethics 90(Supplement) (2009), 393406 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

2 Khalil, E.L., ‘Self-Deception as a Weightless Mask’, Facta Universitatis, Series: Philosophy, Sociology, Psychology, and History 15 (2016), 111 Google Scholar.

3 Cosmides, L. and Tooby, J., ‘Better than Rational: Evolutionary Psychology and the Invisible Hand’, American Economic Review, Papers and Proceedings 84 (1994), 327332 Google Scholar.

4 von Hippel, W. and Trivers, R., ‘The Evolution and Psychology of Self-Deception’, Behavioral and Brain Sciences 34 (2011a), 116 CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

5 von Hippel, W. and Trivers, R., ‘Reflections on Self-Deception’, Behavioral and Brain Sciences 34 (2011b), 4156 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

6 Trivers, R., ‘The Elements of a Scientific Theory of Self-Deception’, Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences 907 (2000), 114131 CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

7 Khalil, E.L., ‘The Weightless Hat: Is Self-Deception Optimal?’, Behavioral and Brain Sciences 34 (2011), 3031 CrossRefGoogle Scholar. (A commentary on W. von Hippel and R. Trivers, ‘The Evolution And Psychology Of Self-Deception’).

8 Khalil, E.L., ‘Self-Deception as a Weightless Mask’, Facta Universitatis, Series: Philosophy, Sociology, Psychology, and History 15 (2016), 111 Google Scholar.

9 Van Leeuwen, D.S.N., ‘The Spandrels of Self-Deception: Prospects for a Biological Theory of a Mental Phenomenon’, Philosophical Psychology 20 (2007), 329348 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

10 Gould, S.J. and Lewontin, R.C., ‘The Spandrels of San Marco and the Panglossian Paradigm: A Critique of the Adaptationist Programme’, Proceedings of Royal Society, London B, 205 (1979), 581–59CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

11 Marciano, A. and Khalil, E.L., ‘Optimization, Path Dependence and the Law: Can Judges Promote Efficiency?’, International Review of Law and Economics 32 (2012), 7282 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

12 Khalil, E.L., ‘Lock-in Institutions and Efficiency’, Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization 88 (2013), 2736 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

13 Mele, A., Self-Deception Unmasked (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2000)Google Scholar.

14 Mele, A., Irrationality: An Essay on Akrasia, Self-Deception, Self-Control (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1987)Google Scholar.

15 Mele, A., ‘Self-Deception and Delusions’, European Journal of Analytic Philosophy (EUJAP) , 2 (2006), 109124 Google Scholar.

16 Erez, A., Johnson, D.E., and Judge, T.A., ‘Self-Deception as a Mediator of the Relationship between Dispositions and Subjective Well-Being’, Personality and Individual Differences 19 (1995), 597–61CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

17 Khalil, E.L., ‘Symbolic Products: Prestige, Pride and Identity Goods’, Theory and Decision 49 (2000), 5377 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

18 Op. cit. note 13.

19 Op. cit. note 14.

20 Davidson, D., ‘Deception and Division’, in Elster, Jon (ed.) The Multiple Self (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1986, 7992)Google Scholar.

21 Davidson, D., ‘Who Is Fooled?’, in Dupuy, J.P. (ed.) Self-Deception and Paradoxes of Rationality (Stanford: CSLI Publications, 1998)Google Scholar.

22 Pears, D., Motivated Irrationality (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1984)Google Scholar.

23 Pears, D., ‘The Goals and Strategies of Self-Deception’, in Elster, J. (ed.) The Multiple Self (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1986)Google Scholar.

24 Taylor, S.E., Positive Illusions: Creative Self-Deception and the Healthy Mind (New York: Basic Books, 1989)Google Scholar.

25 Oxoby, R.J., ‘Attitudes and Allocations: Status, Cognitive Dissonance, and The Manipulation of Attitudes’, Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization 52 (2003), 365–85CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

26 Oxoby, R.J., ‘Cognitive Dissonance, Status, and the Growth of the Underclass’, Economic Journal 114 (2004), 727749 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

27 Bénabou, R. and Tirole, J., ‘Identity, Morals, and Taboos: Beliefs as Assets’, Quarterly Journal of Economics 126 (2011), 805855 CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

28 Aronson, E., The Social Animal (San Francisco: Freeman Press, 1994)Google Scholar.

29 Op. cit. note 27.

30 Young, H.P., ‘Self-Knowledge and Self-Deception’ , unpublished (2007), University of Oxford Google Scholar.

31 Aktipis, C.A., ‘An Evolutionary Perspective on Consciousness: The Role of Emotion, Theory of Mind and Self-Deception’, The Harvard Brain 7 (2000), 2934 Google Scholar.

32 Kurzban, R. and Aktipis, C.A., ‘Modularity and the Social Mind: Are Psychologists too Selfish?’, Personality and Social Psychology Review 11 (2007), 131149 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

33 E.L. Khalil and A. Marciano, ‘A Theory of Tasteful and Distasteful Transactions’, Kyklos (2017), forthcoming.

34 Sachdeva, S., Iliev, R., and Medin, D.L., ‘Sinning Saints and Saintly Sinners: The Paradox of Moral Self-Regulation’, Psychological Science 20 (2009), 523528 CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

35 Merritt, A., Effron, D.A., and Monin, B., ‘Moral Self-Licensing: When Being Good Frees us to be Bad’, Social and Personality Psychology Compass 4/5 (2010), 344357 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

36 Khan, U. and Dhar, R., ‘Licensing Effect in Consumer Choice’, Journal of Marketing Research 43 (2006), 259266 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

37 Op cit. note 35, p. 344.

38 The literature on moral licensing, although nascent and limited, usually fails to define what is moral and what is an immoral act. So, it tends to conflate moral licensing with another phenomenon, viz. equilibrating the marginal utility of different acts. People substitute at the margin different action in order to maximise the overall objective function. For instance, one can become excessively benevolent to others on one day, which would crowd out benevolent actions in the following day. Here, the agent is not using moral credentials as a license to act badly. The agent is rather balancing the scarce resources between two competing preferences, the wellbeing of others vs. the well-being of the self.

39 Akerlof, G.A. and Dickens, W.T., ‘The Economic Consequences of Cognitive Dissonance’, American Economic Review 72 (1982), 307319 Google Scholar.

40 Festinger, L., A Theory of Cognitive Dissonance (Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press, 1957)Google Scholar.

41 Festinger, L., ‘Some Attitudinal Consequences of Forced Decisions’, Acta Psychologica 15 (1959), 389390 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

42 Morris, J. A. and Feldman, D.C., ‘The Dimensions, Antecedents, and Consequences of Emotional Labor’, Academy of Management Review 21 (1996), 9861010 Google Scholar.

43 Lerner, M.J. and Simmons, C.H., ‘Observer's Reaction to the “Innocent Victim”: Compassion or Rejection’, Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 4 (1996), 203210 CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

44 Lerner, M.J., The Belief in a Just World: A Fundamental Delusion (New York: Plenum Press, 1980)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

45 Akerlof, G.A., ‘The Economics of Illusion’, Economics & Politics 1 (1989), 115 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

46 Rabin, M., ‘Cognitive Dissonance and Social Change’, Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization 23 (1994), 177194 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

47 Khalil, E.L., ‘Temptations as Impulsivity: How Far are Regret and the Allais Paradox from Shoplifting?’, Economic Modelling 51 (2015), 551559 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

48 Konow, J., ‘Fair Shares: Accountability and Cognitive Dissonance in Allocation Decisions’, American Economic Review 90 (2000), 10721091 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

49 Dana, J., Weber, R., and Kuang, J., ‘Exploiting Moral Wriggle Room: Experiments Demonstrating an Illusory Preference for Fairness’, Economic Theory 33 (2007), 6780 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

50 Larson, T. and Capra, C.M., ‘Exploiting Moral Wiggle Room: Illusory Preference for Fairness? A Comment’, Judgment and Decision Making 4 (2009), 467474 Google Scholar.

51 Engels, F., ‘Letter to Franz Mehring (1893)’, in Marx and Engels Correspondence (New York: International Publishers, 1968)Google Scholar.

52 Gramsci, A., Selections from the Prison Notebooks of Antonio Gramsci (New York: International Publishers, 1971)Google Scholar.

53 Kuran, T., Private Truths, Public Lies: The Social Consequences of Preference Falsification (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1995)Google Scholar.

54 Khalil, E.L., ‘Review: Timur Kuran's Private Truths, Public Lies: The Social Consequences of Preference Falsification ’, Southern Economic Journal 63 (1996), 269270 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

55 Op. cit. note 28.

56 Nisbett, R.E. and Wilson, T.D., ‘Telling More Than We Can Know: Verbal Reports on Mental Processes’, Psychological Review 84 (1977), 231259 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

57 Wilson, T.D., Strangers to Ourselves: Discovering the Adaptive Unconscious (Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press, 2002)Google Scholar.

58 Wilson, T.D. and Dunn., E.W.Self-Knowledge: Its Limits, Value, and Potential for Improvement’, Annual Review of Psychology 55 (2004), 493518 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

59 Wegner, D.M., ‘Self is Magic’, in Baer, J., Kaufman, J.C., and Baumeister, R.F. (eds) Are we Free? Psychology and Free Will (New York: Oxford University Press, 2008)Google Scholar.

60 Pronin, E., Wegner, D.M., McCarthy, K., and Rodriguez, S., ‘Everyday Magical Powers: The Role of Apparent Mental Causation in the Overestimation of Personal Influence’, Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 91 (2006), 218231 CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

61 Johansson, P., Hall, L., Sikström, S., Tärning, B., and Lind, A., ‘How Something Can be Said about Telling More Than We Can Know: On Choice Blindness and Introspection’, Consciousness and Cognition 15 (2006), 673692 CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

62 Pyszczynski, T., Greenberg, J., and Solomon, S., ‘A Dual-Process Model of Defense Against Conscious and Unconscious Death-Related Thoughts: An Extension of Terror Management Theory’, Psychological Review 106 (1999), 835845 CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

63 Fischhoff, B. and Beyth, R., ‘“I Knew It Would Happen”: Remembered Probabilities of Once-Future Things’, Organizational Behaviour and Human Performance 13 (1975), 116 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

64 Roese, N.J. and Vohs, K.D., ‘Hindsight Bias’, Perspectives on Psychological Science 7 (2012), 411426 CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

65 Yuan, J., Sun, G.-Z., and Siu, R., ‘The Lure of Illusory Luck: How Much Are People Willing to Pay For Random Shocks’, Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization 106 (2014), 269280 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.