1 Introduction
Equivalence of behavior, or bisimilarity in any of its flavors, is a fundamental concept in the study of processes, logic, and many other areas of Computer Science and Mathematics. In the case of discrete (countable) processes, many formalizations of the concept result to be equivalent and it can be completely described by using some form of modal logic—the well-known Hennessy–Milner property.
As soon as one leaves the realm of discrete processes, the question of defining and characterizing behavior turns into a problem with various (sometimes unexpected) mathematical edges. For the case of labelled Markov processes (LMP) [Reference Desharnais3], the first issue to be taken care of is that the concept of probability and measure cannot be defined for all subsets of the state space. Hence the complexity of state spaces (in the sense of Descriptive Set Theory [Reference Kechris7]) plays an important role.
A notable consequence is that an LMP admits two generally different notions of equivalence of behavior between its states: state bisimilarity and event bisimilarity. The first one can be considered as an appropriate generalization to continuous spaces of Larsen and Skou’s probabilistic bisimilarity. On the other hand, event bisimilarity can be characterized by a very simple and natural modal logic $\mathcal {L}$ defined by the following grammar:
where a ranges over possible actions of the interpreting LMP and q over rationals between $0$ and $1$ ; the formula $\langle a \rangle _{>q}\phi $ holds on states at which the probability of reaching another state satisfying $\phi $ after an a transition is greater than q.
Despite its simplicity, this logic also characterizes state bisimilarity for wide classes of LMPs (thus, the two types of bisimilarities coincide). Desharnais, Edalat and Panangaden [Reference Desharnais, Edalat and Panangaden4] showed (building on Edalat’s categorical result [Reference Edalat6]) that the category of generalized LMP over analytic state spaces has the Hennessy–Milner property with respect to $\mathcal {L}$ . This result was later strengthened by Doberkat [Reference Doberkat5] in that it applies to the original category of LMP. Recently, Pachl and the second author extended the result to LMP over universally measurable state spaces [Reference Pachl and Sánchez Terraf9].
But if regularity assumptions on the state spaces are omitted, the Hennessy–Milner property is lost (see [Reference Sánchez Terraf10] by the second author). It is therefore of interest to understand how state bisimilarity differs from the event one for LMP over general measurable spaces. Zhou proposed in [Reference Zhou12] one way to quantify this difference, by expressing state bisimilarity as the greatest fixed point of an operator $\mathcal {O}$ and pointed out an LMP for which more than $\omega $ iterates of $\mathcal {O}$ are needed to reach it.
In this paper, we study the operator $\mathcal {O}$ in a general setting, a dual version $\mathcal {G}$ of it, and the hierarchy of relations and $\sigma $ -algebras respectively induced by them. We then define the Zhou ordinal $\mathfrak {Z}(\mathbb {S})$ of an LMP $\mathbb {S}$ to be the number of iterates needed to reach state bisimilarity when one starts from the event one. After reviewing some basic material in Section 2, we develop the general theory of the operators $\mathcal {O}$ and $\mathcal {G}$ in Section 3. In Section 4 we focus on the class $\mathcal {S}$ of LMP over separable metrizable spaces, “separable LMP” for short, and the supremum of the Zhou ordinals of such processes, $\mathfrak {Z}(\mathcal {S})$ . One of our main results is that $\mathfrak {Z}(\mathcal {S})$ is a limit ordinal of uncountable cofinality (and hence at least $\omega _1$ ). In Section 5, we construct a family of LMPs $\{\mathbb {S}(\beta ) \mid \beta \leq \omega _1\}$ having $\mathfrak {Z}(\mathbb {S}(\beta ))= \beta $ when $\beta $ is a limit ordinal; these processes are separable for countable $\beta $ . We also discuss the consistency with the axioms of set theory that the bound $\omega _1$ is actually attained by a separable LMP. Finally, some further directions are pointed out in Section 6.
2 Preliminaries
An algebra over a set S is a nonempty family of subsets of S closed under finite unions and complementation. It is a $\sigma $ -algebra if it is also closed under countable unions. Given an arbitrary family $\mathcal {U}$ of subsets of S, we use $\sigma (\mathcal {U})$ to denote the least $\sigma $ -algebra over S containing $\mathcal {U}$ . Let $(S,\Sigma )$ be a measurable space, i.e., a set S with a $\sigma $ -algebra $\Sigma $ over S. We say that $(S,\Sigma )$ (or $\Sigma $ ) is countably generated if there is some countable family $\mathcal {U}\subseteq \Sigma $ such that $\Sigma =\sigma (\mathcal {U})$ . A subspace of the measurable space $(S,\Sigma )$ consists of a subset $Y\subseteq S$ with the relative $\sigma $ -algebra . Notice that if $\Sigma =\sigma (\mathcal {U})$ , then . If $(S_1,\Sigma _1),(S_2,\Sigma _2)$ are two measurable spaces, we say that $f:S_1\to S_2$ is $\underline{(\Sigma _1,\Sigma _2)\text{-}\mathrm{measurable}}$ if $f^{-1}(A)\in \Sigma _1$ for all $A\in \Sigma _2$ .
Assume now that $V\subseteq S$ . We will use $\Sigma _V$ to denote $\sigma (\Sigma \cup \{V\})$ , the extension of $\Sigma $ by the set V. It is immediate that $\Sigma _V=\{(B_1\cap V)\cup (B_2\cap V^c)\mid B_1,B_2\in \Sigma \}$ . It is obvious that if $\Sigma $ is countably generated so is $\Sigma _V$ . The sum of two measurable spaces $(S_1,\Sigma _1)$ and $(S_2,\Sigma _2)$ is $(S_1\oplus S_2,\Sigma _1\oplus \Sigma _2)$ , with the following abuse of notation: $S_1\oplus S_2$ is the disjoint union (direct sum qua sets) and $\Sigma _1\oplus \Sigma _2\mathrel {\mathop :}=\{Q_1\oplus Q_2\mid Q_i \in \Sigma _i\}$ . If Y is a topological space, $\mathcal {B}(Y)$ will denote the $\sigma $ -algebra generated by the open sets in Y; hence $(Y,\mathcal {B}(Y))$ is a measurable space, the Borel space of Y. We say that a family of sets $\mathcal {F}\subseteq \mathcal {P}(S)$ separates points if for every pair of distinct points $x,y$ in S, there is some $A\in \mathcal {F}$ with $x\in A$ and $y \notin A$ . We have the following proposition.
Proposition 1. [Reference Kechris7, Proposition 12.1]
Let $(S,\Sigma )$ be a measurable space. The following are equivalent $:$
-
1. $(S,\Sigma )$ is isomorphic to some $(Y,\mathcal {B}(Y))$ , where Y is separable metrizable.
-
2. $(S,\Sigma )$ is isomorphic to some $(Y,\mathcal {B}(Y))$ for $Y\subseteq [0,1]$ .
-
3. $(S,\Sigma )$ is countably generated and separates points.
A class $\mathcal {M}$ of subsets of S is monotone if it is closed under the formation of monotone unions and intersections. Halmos’ Monotone Class Theorem will be frequently used in this work.
Theorem 2. [Reference Billingsley1, Theorem 3.4]
If $\mathcal {F}$ is an algebra of sets and $\mathcal {M}$ is a monotone class, then $\mathcal {F}\subseteq \mathcal {M}$ implies $\sigma (\mathcal {F})\subseteq \mathcal {M}$ .
Given a measurable space $(S,\Sigma )$ , a subprobability measure on S is a $[0,1]$ -valued set function $\mu $ defined on $\Sigma $ such that $\mu (0)=0$ and for any pairwise disjoint collection $\{A_n\mid n\in \omega \}\subseteq \Sigma $ , we have $\mu (\bigcup _{n\in \omega }A_n)=\sum _{n\in \omega }\mu (A_n)$ . In addition, for probability measures we require $\mu (S)=1$ . If $\Sigma \subseteq \Sigma '$ and $\mu ,\mu '$ are measures defined on $(S,\Sigma ),(S,\Sigma ')$ respectively, we say that $\mu '$ extends $\mu $ to $(S,\Sigma ')$ when . A key idea in the construction of examples is the possibility of extending a measure in the following particular way:
Theorem 3. Let $\mu $ be a finite measure defined in $(S,\Sigma )$ and let $V \subseteq S$ be a non- $\mu $ -measurable set. Then there are extensions $\mu _0$ and $\mu _1$ of $\mu $ to $\Sigma _V$ such that $\mu _0(V)\neq \mu _1(V)$ .
Definition 4. A $\underline{\mathrm{Markov\ kernel}}$ on $(S,\Sigma )$ is a function $\tau :S\times \Sigma \rightarrow [0,1]$ such that for each fixed $s \in S$ , $\tau (s,\cdot ):\Sigma \rightarrow [0,1]$ is a subprobability measure, and for each fixed set $X \in \Sigma $ , $\tau (\cdot ,X):S \rightarrow [0,1]$ is $(\Sigma ,\mathcal {B}[0,1])$ -measurable.
These kernels will play the role of transition functions in the processes we define next. Let L be a countable set.
Definition 5. A $\underline{\mathrm{labelled\ Markov\ process (LMP)}}$ with $\underline{\mathrm{label\ set}} \ L$ is a triple $\mathbb {S}=(S,\Sigma ,\{\tau _a \mid a \in L\})$ , where S is a set of $\underline{\mathrm{states}}$ , $\Sigma $ is a $\sigma $ -algebra over S, and for each $a\in L$ , $\tau _a:S \times \Sigma \rightarrow [0,1]$ is a Markov kernel. An LMP is said to be $\underline{\mathrm{separable}}$ if its state space is countably generated and separates points.
By Proposition 1, the restriction to separable LMP is equivalent to studying processes whose state space is a subset of Euclidean space.
Example 6. We will now present the LMP $\mathbb {U}$ , which was introduced (under the name $\mathbf {S_3}$ ) in [Reference Sánchez Terraf10]. This will be an important example throughout this paper to illustrate concepts and motivate constructions. From this point onwards, I will denote the open interval $(0,1)$ , $\mathfrak {m}$ will be the Lebesgue measure on I and $\mathcal {B}_V$ will be the $\sigma $ -algebra $\sigma (\mathcal {B}(I) \cup \{V\})$ , where V is a Lebesgue non-measurable subset of $I $ . By Theorem 3 we have two extensions $\mathfrak {m}_0$ and $\mathfrak {m}_1$ of $\mathfrak {m}$ such that $\mathfrak {m}_0(V)\neq \mathfrak {m}_1(V)$ . Also, let $\{q_n\}_{n\in \omega }$ be an enumeration of the rationals in I and define $B_n \mathrel {\mathop :}= (0,q_n)$ ; hence $\{B_n\mid n\in \omega \}$ is a countable generating family of $\mathcal {B}(I )$ .
Let $s,t,x \notin I $ be mutually distinct; we may view $\mathfrak {m}_0$ and $\mathfrak {m}_1$ as measures defined on the sum $I \oplus \{s,t,x\}$ , supported on $I $ . The label set will be $L\mathrel {\mathop :}= \omega \cup \{\infty \}$ . Now define $\mathbb {U}=(U,\Upsilon ,\{\tau _n \mid n\in L\})$ such that
when $n\in \omega $ and $A\in \Upsilon $ . This defines an LMP since for all r, $0\leq \chi _{B_a}(r) \leq 1$ and ${0\leq \chi _{\{s\}}(r) + \chi _{\{t\}}(r) \leq 1}$ and we infer measurability because $\tau _l(\cdot ,A)$ is always a linear combination of measurable functions.
The dynamics of this process goes intuitively as follows: The states s and t can only make an $\infty $ -labelled transition to a “uniformly distributed” state in $I $ , but they disagree on the probability of reaching $V\subseteq I$ . Then, each point of $B_n\subseteq I$ can make an n-transition to x. Finally, x can make no transition at all (see Figure 1).
For R a symmetric relation over S, we say that $A \subseteq S$ is R-closed if $\{s\in S \mid \exists x\in A \; x\mathrel {R}s\} \subseteq A$ . If $\Gamma \subseteq \mathcal {P}(S)$ , we denote by $\Gamma (R)$ the family of all R-closed sets in $\Gamma $ . Note that if $\Gamma $ is a $\sigma $ -algebra, then $\Gamma (R)$ is a sub- $\sigma $ -algebra of $\Gamma $ . We also define a new relation $\mathcal {R}(\Gamma )$ consisting of all pairs $(s,t)$ such that $\forall A \in \Gamma \; (s \in A \leftrightarrow t \in A)$ .
Definition 7. Fix an LMP $\mathbb {S}=(S,\Sigma ,\{\tau _a\mid a\in L\})$ . A $\underline{\mathrm{state\ bisimulation}} \ R$ on $\mathbb {S}$ is a symmetric relation on S such that $\forall a\in L \; \tau _a(s,C)=\tau _a(t,C)$ whenever $s\mathrel {R}t$ and $C \in \Sigma (R)$ . We say that s and t are $\underline{\mathrm{state\ bisimilar}}$ , denoted by $s\sim _s t$ , if there exists some state bisimulation R such that $s\mathrel {R}t$ . The relation $\sim _s$ is called $\underline{\mathrm{state\ bisimilarity}}$ .
Definition 8. Let $\mathbb {S}=(S,\Sigma ,\{\tau _a \mid a\in L\})$ be an LMP and $\Lambda \subseteq \Sigma $ . $\Lambda $ is $\underline{\mathrm{stable}}$ with respect to $\mathbb {S}$ if for all $A \in \Lambda $ , $r \in [0,1]\cap \mathbb {Q}$ and $a \in L$ , we have $\{s : \tau _a(s,A)>r\} \in \Lambda $ .
Note that for a sub- $\sigma $ -algebra $\Lambda \subseteq \Sigma $ , $\Lambda $ is stable if and only if is an LMP.
Definition 9. Let $\mathbb {S}=(S,\Sigma ,\{\tau _a \mid a\in L\})$ be an LMP. A relation R on S will be called an $\underline{\mathrm{event\ bisimulation}}$ if there exists a stable sub- $\sigma $ -algebra $\Lambda \subseteq \Sigma $ such that $R=\mathcal {R}(\Lambda )$ .
Two states s and t of an LMP are $\underline{\mathrm{event\ bisimilar}}$ , denoted by $s\sim _e t$ , if there exists some event bisimulation R such that $s\mathrel {R}t$ . The relation $\sim _e$ is called $\underline{\mathrm{event\ bisimilarity}}$ .
To illustrate these concepts with the LMP $\mathbb {U}$ , one can show that $\Xi \mathrel {\mathop :}= \sigma (\mathcal {B}(I) \cup \{\{s,t\},\{x\}\})$ is a stable $\sigma $ -algebra; hence s and t are event bisimilar. However they are not state bisimilar as V is $\mathcal {R}(\sim _s)$ -closed and $\tau _{\infty }(s,V)\neq \tau _{\infty }(t,V)$ . See [Reference Sánchez Terraf10] for details.
Recall the modal logic $\mathcal {L}$ presented in the Introduction. We spell out the formal interpretation of the modalities: $s \models \langle a \rangle _{>q}\phi $ on the LMP $(S,\Sigma ,\{\tau _a \mid a\in L\})$ if and only if there exists $A \in \Sigma $ such that for all $s' \in A$ , $s' \models \phi $ and $\tau _a(s,A)> q$ . Given a formula $\phi $ we write to denote the set of states satisfying $\phi $ . It can be proved by induction that each of these sets is measurable. We write for the collection of sets ; we have the following logical characterization of event bisimilarity.
Theorem 10. [Reference Danos, Desharnais, Laviolette and Panangaden2, Proposition 5.5 and Corollary 5.6]
For an LMP $(S,\Sigma ,\{\tau _a \mid a\in L\})$ , is the smallest stable $\sigma $ -algebra included in $\Sigma $ . Therefore the logic $\mathcal {L}$ characterizes event bisimilarity, in symbols .
The last equality follows easily from the fact that $\mathcal {R}(\sigma (\mathcal {F}))=\mathcal {R}(\mathcal {F})$ holds for any family of sets $\mathcal {F}$ .
Regarding $\mathbb {U}$ , the $\sigma $ -algebra $\Xi $ turns out to be ; therefore ${\sim _e}=\textrm {id}_U\cup \{(s,t),(t,s)\}$ . This further implies that ${\sim _s}=\textrm {id}_U$ given that it can be proved that ${\sim _s}\subseteq {\sim _e}$ is always the case and, as noted before, s and t are not state-bisimilar. Consequently, this is an example where state bisimilarity is properly contained in event bisimilarity. In fact, the LMP $\mathbb {U}$ was introduced in [Reference Sánchez Terraf10] to show that event bisimilarity and state bisimilarity differ in LMP over general measurable spaces. In this work it will serve as a seed for several constructions to be performed in Section 4.
3 The operators $\mathcal {O}$ and $\mathcal {G}$
Fix a Markov process $\mathbb {S}=(S,\Sigma ,\{\tau _a\mid a\in L\})$ . We will work with the operators defined in [Reference Zhou12], and we introduce a new one, $\mathcal {G}$ :
Definition 11. Let $\Lambda \subseteq \Sigma $ and $R \subseteq S\times S$ .
-
• The relation $\mathcal {R}^T(\Lambda )$ is given by
$$\begin{align*}(s,t) \in \mathcal{R}^T(\Lambda) \iff \forall a\in L \; \forall E\in \Lambda \; \tau_a(s,E)=\tau_a(t,E). \end{align*}$$ -
• $\mathcal {O}(R)\mathrel {\mathop :}= \mathcal {R}^T(\Sigma (R))$ .
-
• $\mathcal {G}(\Lambda )\mathrel {\mathop :}= \Sigma (\mathcal {R}^T(\Lambda ))$ .
Note that $\mathcal {O}(R)$ is always an equivalence relation for any R and if $\Lambda $ is a $\sigma $ -algebra, then $\mathcal {G}(\Lambda )$ is too. The motivating idea behind the definition of $\mathcal {R}^T$ is to relate states that are probabilistically indistinguishable with respect to a fixed set of “tests,” here given by the family $\Lambda $ of events. An equivalence relation R on the set of states induces naturally $\Sigma (R)$ , the R-closed sets in $\Sigma $ , as a family of tests. It follows that R is a state bisimulation if and only if $R\subseteq \mathcal {R}^T(\Sigma (R)) = \mathcal {O}(R)$ .
Example 12. Let us do some simple calculations with the operator $\mathcal {O}$ concerning the LMP $\mathbb {U}$ . If $\nabla $ denotes the total relation $U\times U$ ,
Also, because $V \in \Upsilon (\sim _e)$ ,
We highlight the fact that a single application of $\mathcal {O}$ from the event bisimilarity $\sim _e$ leads to state bisimilarity $\sim _s$ .
In the next proposition we collect some basic facts on the operators defined up to this point; most of them appear in [Reference Zhou12].
Proposition 13. Let $\Lambda , \Lambda '\subseteq \Sigma $ be sub- $\sigma $ -algebras and $R, R'\subseteq S\times S$ .
-
1. $\Lambda \subseteq \Sigma (\mathcal {R}(\Lambda ))$ .
-
2. $R\subseteq \mathcal {R}(\Sigma (R))$ .
-
3. If $\Lambda \subseteq \Lambda '$ , then $\mathcal {R}(\Lambda )\supseteq \mathcal {R}(\Lambda ')$ and $\mathcal {R}^T(\Lambda )\supseteq \mathcal {R}^T(\Lambda ')$ .
-
4. If $R\subseteq R'$ , then $\Sigma (R)\supseteq \Sigma (R')$ .
-
5. $\mathcal {R}(\Sigma (\mathcal {R}(\Lambda )))=\mathcal {R}(\Lambda )$ .
-
6. $\mathcal {O}$ and $\mathcal {G}$ are monotone operators.
-
7. R is a state bisimulation iff $(S,\Sigma (R),\{\tau _a\mid a \in L\})$ is an LMP.
-
8. If $\Lambda $ is stable, then $\mathcal {R}(\Lambda )\subseteq \mathcal {R}^T(\Lambda )$ .
We will also need some basic material on fixpoint theory. We work with von Neumann ordinals, viz. $\alpha = \{\gamma : \gamma < \alpha \}$ . If $F:A\to A$ is a function on a complete lattice A, we define the iterates of F by $F^0(x)\mathrel {\mathop :}= x$ , $F^{\alpha +1}(x)\mathrel {\mathop :}= F(F^{\alpha }(x))$ , $F^{\lambda }(x)\mathrel {\mathop :}=\bigwedge _{\alpha <\lambda }F^{\alpha }(x)$ if $\lambda $ is a limit ordinal, and $F^{\infty }(x)=\bigwedge _{\lambda }F^{\lambda }(x)$ . We say that x is a pre-fixpoint (resp. post-fixpoint) of F if $F(x)\leq x$ (resp. $x\leq F(x)$ ).
Proposition 14. [Reference Sangiorgi11, Exercise 2.8.10]
Let $F:A\to A$ be a monotone function on a complete lattice A. If x is a pre-fixpoint of F, then $F^{\infty }(x)$ is the greatest fixpoint of F below x. Furthermore, this fixed point is reached at an ordinal $\alpha $ such that $|\alpha |\leq |A|$ .
As in Zhou’s work [Reference Zhou12] we will construct chains of relations and of $\sigma $ -algebras using the operators $\mathcal {O}$ and $\mathcal {G}$ . The next result will be an aid in showing that (resp. ) is a post(pre)-fixpoint of $\mathcal {G}$ ( $\mathcal {O}$ ).
Lemma 15. .
Proof. Since is stable, we have by Proposition 13(8). We prove the other inclusion by structural induction on formulas. Suppose that . If , then $s \in A \Leftrightarrow t \in A$ . The case is also trivial from the IH. For the case , observe that the hypothesis implies . Then, the $\sigma $ -algebra $\mathcal {A}_{s,t}\mathrel {\mathop :}= \{A\in \Sigma \mid s\in A \Leftrightarrow t\in A\}$ includes . We conclude that , i.e., .
Corollary 16. and $\mathcal {O}(\sim _e)\subseteq {\sim _e}$ .
Proof. Since $\Sigma \circ \mathcal {R}$ is expansive by Proposition 13(1), the previous lemma implies that
. Moreover, by antimonotonicity of $\mathcal {R}^T$ we obtain the result for $\mathcal {O}$ :
The inclusions $\mathcal {O}(R)\subseteq R$ and $\Lambda \subseteq \mathcal {G}(\Lambda )$ do not hold in general for arbitrary R and $\Lambda $ . For example, if $\tau $ is null for all arguments, $\mathcal {O}(R) =S\times S$ for any relation R and analogously for $\mathcal {G}$ .
Given a relation R we define a transfinite sequence of equivalence relations using the operator $\mathcal {O}$ :
-
• $\mathcal {O}^0(R)\mathrel {\mathop :}= R$ .
-
• $\mathcal {O}^{\alpha +1}(R)\mathrel {\mathop :}= \mathcal {O}(\mathcal {O}^{\alpha }(R))$ .
-
• $\mathcal {O}^{\lambda }(R)\mathrel {\mathop :}= \bigcap _{\alpha < \lambda }\mathcal {O}^{\alpha }(R)$ if $\lambda $ is a limit.
Similarly, if $\Lambda \subseteq \Sigma $ is a $\sigma $ -algebra, $\mathcal {G}$ generates a family of $\sigma $ -algebras given by:
-
• $\mathcal {G}^0(\Lambda )\mathrel {\mathop :}= \Lambda $ .
-
• $\mathcal {G}^{\alpha +1}(\Lambda )\mathrel {\mathop :}= \mathcal {G}(\mathcal {G}^{\alpha }(\Lambda ))$ .
-
• $\mathcal {G}^{\lambda }(\Lambda )\mathrel {\mathop :}= \sigma (\bigcup _{\alpha < \lambda } \mathcal {G}{^{\alpha }}(\Lambda ))$ if $\lambda $ is a limit ordinal.
Note that in the limit case of this last definition we must take the generated $\sigma $ -algebra since the union of a countable chain of $\sigma $ -algebras is not in general a $\sigma $ -algebra.
Let $\Sigma _0 \subseteq \Sigma $ be a sub- $\sigma $ -algebra and $R_0\subseteq S\times S$ a relation. From the iterates of $\mathcal {O}$ and $\mathcal {G}$ we define new $\sigma $ -algebras and relations.
Definition 17. For every ordinal $\alpha $ let $\Sigma _{\alpha }\mathrel {\mathop :}= \mathcal {G}^{\alpha }(\Sigma _0)$ and $R_{\alpha }\mathrel {\mathop :}= \mathcal {O}^{\alpha }(R_0)$ .
It is clear that if $\alpha <\lambda $ , then $R_{\lambda }\subseteq R_{\alpha }$ since $R_{\lambda }=\mathcal {O}^{\lambda }(R_0)=\bigcap _{\beta < \lambda }\mathcal {O}^{\beta }(R_0)=\bigcap _{\beta < \lambda }R_{\beta }\subseteq R_{\alpha }$ . It is also easy to verify from the definitions that $\Sigma _{\alpha } \subseteq \Sigma _{\lambda }$ . We are interested in determining what other relationships hold among these relations and $\sigma $ -algebras. We are mainly concerned in the case in which and when $R_0$ is the relation of event bisimilarity; then by Lemma 15 we have $R_0=\mathcal {R}^T(\Sigma _0)$ .
Proposition 18. If $R_0=\mathcal {R}^T(\Sigma _0)$ , then for all $\alpha $ , $R_{\alpha } = \mathcal {R}^T(\Sigma _{\alpha })$ .
Proof. By induction on $\alpha $ . The case $\alpha =0$ is included in the hypothesis. Now assume that it holds for $\alpha $ . We calculate as follows: $R_{\alpha +1}\ {=}\ \mathcal {O}^{\alpha +1}(R_0)\ {=}\ \mathcal {O}(\mathcal {O}^{\alpha }(R_0))\ {=}\ \mathcal {O}(R_{\alpha })=\mathcal {R}^T(\Sigma (R_{\alpha }))\ {=}\ \mathcal {R}^T(\Sigma (\mathcal {R}^T(\Sigma _{\alpha })))\ {=}\ \mathcal {R}^T(\mathcal {G}(\Sigma _{\alpha }))\ {=}\ \mathcal {R}^T(\mathcal {G}(\mathcal {G}^{\alpha }(\Sigma _0))\ {=}\ \mathcal {R}^T(\mathcal {G}^{\alpha +1}(\Sigma _0)){=}\mathcal {R}^T(\Sigma _{\alpha +1})$ . Then it holds for $\alpha +1$ .
Suppose now that the result holds for all $\alpha <\lambda $ , with $\lambda $ a limit ordinal. We have $R_{\lambda }=\mathcal {O}^{\lambda }(R_0)=\bigcap _{\alpha <\lambda }\mathcal {O}^{\alpha }(R_0)=\bigcap _{\alpha <\lambda }R_{\alpha }=\bigcap _{\alpha <\lambda }\mathcal {R}^T(\Sigma _{\alpha })$ . We will prove that the last term equals $\mathcal {R}^T(\bigcup _{\alpha <\lambda }\Sigma _{\alpha })$ . Let $s,t \in S$ . Then
Claim. $\mathcal {R}^T(\bigcup _{\alpha <\lambda }\Sigma _{\alpha })=\mathcal {R}^T(\sigma (\bigcup _{\alpha <\lambda }\Sigma _{\alpha }))$ .
With this we can conclude since
Now we prove the claim. Let $s,t \in S$ such that $(s,t)\in \mathcal {R}^T(\bigcup _{\alpha <\lambda }\Sigma _{\alpha })$ . We define ${\mathcal {D}_{s,t}\mathrel {\mathop :}=\{A\in \Sigma \mid \forall a\in L, \, \tau _a(s,A)=\tau _a(t,A)\}}$ . We check that $\mathcal {D}_{s,t}$ is a monotone class on S. If $\{A_i\}_{i\in \omega }$ is an increasing family of subsets S such that $A_i\in \mathcal {D}_{s,t}$ , upper continuity of the measures $\tau _a(s,\cdot )$ and $\tau _a(t,\cdot )$ implies
We argue similarly for an intersection of a decreasing family in $\mathcal {D}_{s,t}$ by using lower continuity of the (finite) measures involved. Since, by hypothesis, $\bigcup _{\alpha <\lambda }\Sigma _{\alpha } \subseteq \mathcal {D}_{s,t}$ and moreover, the family $\bigcup _{\alpha <\lambda }\Sigma _{\alpha }$ is an algebra of subsets of S, the Monotone Class Theorem yields $\sigma (\bigcup _{\alpha <\lambda }\Sigma _{\alpha })\subseteq \mathcal {D}_{s,t}$ .
Since the reverse inclusion $\mathcal {R}^T(\bigcup _{\alpha <\lambda }\Sigma _{\alpha })\supseteq \mathcal {R}^T(\sigma (\bigcup _{\alpha <\lambda }\Sigma _{\alpha }))$ is trivial, we have the result.
Corollary 19. If $R_0=\mathcal {R}^T(\Sigma _0)$ , then for all $\alpha $ , $\Sigma (R_{\alpha })=\Sigma _{\alpha +1}$ .
Proof. Unfolding definitions,
Proposition 20. If $R_0=\mathcal {R}(\Sigma _0)=\mathcal {R}^T(\Sigma _0)$ , then for all $\alpha $ , $R_{\alpha +1}\subseteq R_{\alpha }$ .
Proof. We work by induction on $\alpha $ . By using the antimonotonicity of $\mathcal {R}^T$ and $\Sigma (\mathcal {R}(\Sigma _0))\supseteq \Sigma _0$ we have
This shows the base case. Assume the result for $\alpha $ , then by applying the monotonicity of $\mathcal {O}$ to the IH, we have $R_{\alpha +2}=\mathcal {O}(R_{\alpha +1})\subseteq \mathcal {O}(R_{\alpha })=R_{\alpha +1}$ .
For limit $\lambda $ we observe that for all $\alpha <\lambda $ monotonicity of $\mathcal {O}$ and IH ensure ${R_{\lambda +1}=\mathcal {O}(R_{\lambda })\subseteq \mathcal {O}(R_{\alpha })=R_{\alpha +1}\subseteq R_{\alpha }}$ . Then, $R_{\lambda +1}\subseteq \bigcap _{\alpha < \lambda }R_{\alpha }=R_{\lambda }$ .
Corollary 21. If $R_0=\mathcal {R}(\Sigma _0)=\mathcal {R}^T(\Sigma _0)$ , then for all $\alpha $ , $\Sigma _{\alpha }\subseteq \Sigma _{\alpha +1}$ .
Proof. For $\alpha =0$ we observe that $\Sigma _0\subseteq \Sigma (\mathcal {R}(\Sigma _0))=\Sigma (\mathcal {R}^T(\Sigma _0))=\mathcal {G}(\Sigma _0)=\Sigma _1$ . For successor ordinals, we use Propositions 18 and 20 to obtain
Finally, for the limit case, observe that for all $\alpha <\lambda $ , $\Sigma _{\alpha }\subseteq \Sigma _{\lambda }$ ; then by IH and monotonicity of $\mathcal {G}$ we have $\Sigma _{\alpha }\subseteq \Sigma _{\alpha +1}=\mathcal {G}(\Sigma _{\alpha })\subseteq \mathcal {G}(\Sigma _{\lambda })=\Sigma _{\lambda +1}$ . Therefore $\Sigma _{\lambda }=\sigma (\bigcup _{\alpha < \lambda }\Sigma _{\alpha })\subseteq \Sigma _{\lambda +1}$ .
In the following, for any $Q\in \Sigma $ , ${\langle a \rangle _{\leq q}}Q$ will denote the set $\{s\in S \mid \tau _a(s,Q)\leq q \}$ . Similarly for the other order relations.
Note 22. If $\Theta $ is a $\sigma $ -algebra, a relation $\mathcal {R}^T(\Theta )$ is of the form $\mathcal {R}(\mathcal {F})$ for some subfamily $\mathcal {F}$ of $\Sigma $ : If $\Gamma $ is any algebra such that $\sigma (\Gamma )=\Theta $ , then
Let $\mathcal {F}$ the family on the right-hand side, namely $\{{\langle a \rangle _{\leq q}}Q \mid a\in L,\, q\in \mathbb {Q},\, Q\in \Gamma \}$ . If $(s,t)\in \mathcal {R}^T(\Theta )$ , then for any $a\in L$ , $q\in \mathbb {Q}$ and $Q\in \Theta $ , we have $s\in {\langle a \rangle _{\leq q}}Q$ iff $\tau _a(s,Q)\leq q$ iff $\tau _a(t,Q)\leq q$ iff $t\in {\langle a \rangle _{\leq q}}Q$ . Conversely, suppose that $(s,t)\in \mathcal {R}(\mathcal {F})$ . Since $\mathcal {D}_{s,t}=\{Q\in \Theta \mid \forall a\in L, \, \tau _a(s,Q)=\tau _a(t,Q)\}$ is a monotone class and $\Gamma $ is a generating algebra for $\Theta $ such that $\Gamma \subseteq \mathcal {D}_{s,t}$ , the Monotone Class Theorem yields $\Theta =\sigma (\Gamma )\subseteq \mathcal {D}_{s,t}$ for every $a\in L$ .
Proposition 23. If $R_0=\mathcal {R}(\Sigma _0)=\mathcal {R}^T(\Sigma _0)$ , then for all limit ordinals $\lambda $ , $\mathcal {R}(\Sigma _{\lambda })=\mathcal {R}^T(\Sigma _{\lambda })$ .
Proof. By Note 22 there is some $\Lambda \subseteq \Sigma $ such that $\mathcal {R}^T(\Sigma _{\alpha })=\mathcal {R}(\Lambda )$ . From Proposition 13(5) it follows that
If $\lambda $ is a limit ordinal, $\Sigma _{\alpha +1}\subseteq \Sigma _{\lambda }$ holds for all $\alpha <\lambda $ and hence $\mathcal {R}(\Sigma _{\lambda })\subseteq \mathcal {R}(\Sigma _{\alpha +1})=\mathcal {R}^T(\Sigma _{\alpha })=R_{\alpha }$ . Then, $\mathcal {R}(\Sigma _{\lambda })\subseteq \bigcap _{\alpha <\lambda }R_{\alpha }=R_{\lambda }=\mathcal {R}^T(\Sigma _{\lambda })=\mathcal {R}(\Sigma _{\lambda +1})\subseteq \mathcal {R}(\Sigma _{\lambda })$ and the result follows.
In Section 5 we will construct an LMP for which $\mathcal {R}(\Sigma _{\alpha +1})\supsetneq \mathcal {R}^T(\Sigma _{\alpha +1})$ , and hence the previous equality does not hold for successor ordinals in general.
In the case $R_0=\mathcal {R}(\Sigma _0)=\mathcal {R}^T(\Sigma _0)$ , we may summarize the results up to this point in Figure 2:
Corollary 24. For a limit ordinal $\lambda $ , if $\Sigma (\mathcal {R}(\Sigma _{\lambda }))=\Sigma _{\lambda }$ , then $\mathcal {R}(\Sigma _{\lambda })$ is a state bisimulation.
Proof. $\mathcal {R}^T(\Sigma (\mathcal {R}(\Sigma _{\lambda })))=\mathcal {R}^T(\Sigma _{\lambda })=\mathcal {R}(\Sigma _{\lambda })$ . Therefore $\mathcal {R}(\Sigma _{\lambda })$ is a state bisimulation.
We add an observation about Figure 2: If $\mathcal {G}(\Gamma )=\Gamma $ , then $\mathcal {O}(\mathcal {R}^T(\Gamma ))=\mathcal {R}^T\Sigma (\mathcal {R}^T(\Gamma ))=\mathcal {R}^T(\mathcal {G}(\Gamma ))=\mathcal {R}^T(\Gamma )$ . This means that a fixpoint in the lower part forces a fixpoint in the upper part. By using the example in [Reference Sánchez Terraf10] it can be seen that the converse does not hold.
Lemma 25. Let $\Lambda $ be a sub- $\sigma $ -algebra of $\Sigma $ such that $\Sigma (\mathcal {R}(\Lambda ))=\Lambda $ . The following are equivalent $:$
-
1. $\Lambda $ is stable.
-
2. $\mathcal {R}(\Lambda ) \subseteq \mathcal {R}^T(\Lambda )$ .
-
3. $\mathcal {R}(\Lambda )$ is a state bisimulation.
Proof. 1 implies 2 by Proposition 13(8). For 2 $\Rightarrow $ 3, observe that $\mathcal {R}(\Lambda )\subseteq \mathcal {R}^T(\Lambda )=\mathcal {R}^T(\Sigma (\mathcal {R}(\Lambda )))$ and this means that $\mathcal {R}(\Lambda )$ is a state bisimulation.
By virtue of Proposition 13, Item 7 implies $(S,\Sigma (\mathcal {R}(\Lambda )),\tau )$ is an LMP, but then $\Sigma (\mathcal {R}(\Lambda ))=\Lambda $ is stable.
Example. The hypothesis is necessary $:$ On $[0,1]$ , take $\Sigma =\mathcal {B}([0,1])$ , $\Lambda $ to be the countable-cocountable $\sigma $ -algebra and $\tau (x,A)\mathrel {\mathop :}= \delta _x(A)$ for $x\in [0,\frac {1}{2}]$ and $\tau (x,A)\mathrel {\mathop :}= \frac {1}{2} \delta _x(A)$ if $x\in (\frac {1}{2},1]$ . Then $\Sigma (\mathcal {R}(\Lambda ))=\Sigma \neq \Lambda $ , $\mathcal {R}(\Lambda )=\textrm {id}_{[0,1]}=\mathcal {R}^T(\Lambda )$ and $\Lambda $ is not stable since, e.g., $\{x \mid \tau (x,[0,1])>\frac {1}{2}\}=[0,\frac {1}{2}]\notin \Lambda $ . This example shows that 2 does not imply 1 in general. Since the identity relation is a state bisimulation, we also conclude that 3 does not imply 1 in general.
The $\sigma $ -algebra $\Sigma _{\omega }$ corresponding to the LMP to be presented in Section 5, satisfies $\mathcal {R}^T(\Sigma _{\omega })=\mathcal {R}(\Sigma _{\omega })$ but $\mathcal {R}(\Sigma _{\omega })$ is not a state bisimulation. Hence 2 does not imply 3 in general. This example has a stable $\Sigma _0$ but $R_0=\mathcal {R}(\Sigma _0)$ is not state bisimulation; hence 1 does not imply 3.
We now aim to prove that $\Sigma _{\lambda }$ is stable for limit $\lambda $ . With the notation introduced before Note 22, we observe that $\Gamma $ is stable if and only if $\forall a \in L \; \forall q \in \mathbb {Q} \; \forall Q\in \Gamma \; \langle a \rangle _{\leq q}Q \in \Gamma $ . Given a label a, we define the following set:
Then, to show that $\Sigma _{\lambda }$ is stable it is enough to prove $\Sigma _{\lambda } \subseteq \mathcal {A}_a$ for all $a\in L$ .
Lemma 26. If $\lambda $ is a limit ordinal, then $\forall a \in L \, \forall \alpha <\lambda \; \Sigma _{\alpha } \subseteq \mathcal {A}_a$ .
Proof. Let $\alpha <\lambda $ and $Q\in \Sigma _{\alpha }$ . We will show that for every label $a\in L$ and for all $q\in \mathbb {Q}$ the sets $\langle a\rangle _{\leq q}Q$ and $\langle a\rangle _{<q}Q$ are in $\Sigma _{\alpha +1}=\Sigma (\mathcal {R}^T(\Sigma _{\alpha }))\subseteq \Sigma _{\lambda }$ . Since $\tau _a(\cdot ,Q)$ is measurable, $\langle a\rangle _{\leq q}Q=\tau _a(\cdot , Q)^{-1}((0,q]) \in \Sigma $ . To check that $\langle a\rangle _{\leq q}Q$ is $\mathcal {R}^T(\Sigma _{\alpha })$ -closed, note that
The proof for $\langle a \rangle _{<q}Q$ is similar.
Lemma 27.
-
1. If $\{A_n\}_{n \in \omega }$ is a non-decreasing sequence of measurable sets, then for all $a\in L$ and for all $q\in \mathbb {Q}$ , $\langle a \rangle _{\leq q}\bigcup _{n\in \omega }A_n=\bigcap _{n\in \omega }\langle a \rangle _{\leq q}A_n$ .
-
2. If $\{B_n\}_{n\in \omega }$ is a non-increasing sequence of measurable sets, then for all $a\in L$ and for all $q\in \mathbb {Q}$ , $\langle a \rangle _{< q}\bigcap _{n\in \omega }B_n=\bigcup _{n\in \omega }\langle a \rangle _{<q}B_n$ .
-
3. $\mathcal {A}_a$ is a monotone class.
Proof.
-
1. In general, if $A\subseteq B$ , then $\langle a \rangle _{\leq q}B\subseteq \langle a \rangle _{\leq q}A$ by monotonicity of measures. Thus we have ( $\subseteq $ ). For ( $\supseteq $ ), if $s\in S$ satisfies $\forall n\in \omega \, \tau _a(s,A_n)\leq q$ , the continuity of the measure $\tau _a(s,\cdot )$ yields $\tau _a(s,\bigcup _{n\in \omega }A_n)=\lim \tau _a(s,A_n)\leq q$ .
-
2. Similarly to 1,
$$\begin{align*}\textstyle\bigcap_{n\in\omega}B_n\subseteq B_m &\implies \langle a \rangle_{<q}\bigcap_{n\in\omega}B_n\supseteq \langle a \rangle_{<q}B_m \\&\implies \langle a \rangle_{<q}\bigcap_{n\in\omega}B_n \supseteq \bigcup_{m\in\omega} \langle a \rangle_{<q}B_m. \end{align*}$$For the other inclusion, if $s\in \langle a \rangle _{<q}\bigcap _{n\in \omega }B_n $ , continuity of the measure $\tau _a(s,\cdot )$ implies $q>\tau _a(s,\bigcap _{n\in \omega }B_n)=\lim \tau (s,B_n)$ . Then, there exists $n\in \omega $ such that $\tau _a(s,B_n)<q$ and hence $s\in \langle a \rangle _{<q}B_n$ .
-
3. Let $\{A_n\}_{n \in \omega }\subseteq \mathcal {A}_a$ be a non-decreasing sequence of sets. Let $q\in \mathbb {Q}$ ; part 1 allows us to conclude $\langle a \rangle _{\leq q}\bigcup _{n\in \omega }A_n=\bigcap _{n\in \omega }\langle a \rangle _{\leq q}A_n\in \Sigma _{\lambda }$ and also
$$\begin{align*}\textstyle \langle a \rangle _{<q}\bigcup_{n\in \omega}A_n\kern1.2pt{=}\kern1.2pt\bigcup_{m\in\omega}\langle a \rangle_{\leq q-1/m}(\bigcup_{n\in \omega}A_n)\kern1.2pt{=}\kern1.2pt\bigcup_{m\in\omega}\bigcap_{n\in \omega}(\langle a \rangle_{\leq q-1/m}A_n) \kern1.2pt{\in}\kern1.2pt \Sigma_{\lambda}. \end{align*}$$Then, $\bigcup _{n\in \omega }A_n \in \mathcal {A}_a$ .
Now let $\{B_n\}_{n \in \omega }\subseteq \mathcal {A}_a$ be non-increasing and let $q\in \mathbb {Q}$ . The second part yields $\langle a \rangle _{<q}\bigcap _{n\in \omega }B_n=\bigcup _{n\in \omega }\langle a \rangle _{<q}B_n\in \Sigma _{\lambda }$ and also
$$\begin{align*}\textstyle \langle a \rangle _{\leq q}\bigcap_{n\in \omega}B_n\kern1.2pt{=}\kern1.2pt\bigcap_{m\in\omega}\langle a \rangle_{<q+1/m}(\bigcap_{n\in \omega}B_n)\kern1.2pt{=}\bigcap_{m\in\omega}\bigcup_{n\in \omega}(\langle a \rangle_{<q+1/m}B_n) \kern1.2pt{\in}\kern1.2pt \Sigma_{\lambda}. \end{align*}$$Then, $\bigcap _{n\in \omega }B_n \in \mathcal {A}_a$ .
Theorem 28. $\Sigma _{\lambda }$ is a stable $\sigma $ -algebra for any limit ordinal $\lambda $ .
4 The Zhou Ordinal
Zhou expressed state bisimilarity as a fixpoint:
Theorem 29. [Reference Zhou12, Theorem 3.4]
State bisimilarity $\sim _s$ is the greatest fixpoint of $\mathcal {O}$ .
By direct application of Proposition 14 we get the following:
Theorem 30. Let R be an equivalence relation on S such that ${\sim _s}\subseteq R$ and $\mathcal {O}(R)\subseteq R$ , then there exists an ordinal $\alpha $ such that $|\alpha |\leq |S|$ and $\mathcal {O}^{\alpha }(R)={\sim _s}$ .
Corollary 31. [Reference Zhou12, Theorem 4.1]
State bisimilarity $\sim _s$ can be obtained by iterating $\mathcal {O}$ from the total relation or from event bisimilarity $\sim _e$ .
Thanks to this result we may define the following concept.
Definition 32. The $\underline{\mathrm{Zhou\ ordinal}}$ of an LMP $\mathbb {S}$ , denoted $\mathfrak {Z}(\mathbb {S})$ , is the minimum $\alpha $ such that $\mathcal {O}^{\alpha }(\sim _e)={\sim _s}$ . The Zhou ordinal of a class $\mathcal {A}$ of processes, denoted $\mathfrak {Z}(\mathcal {A})$ , is the supremum of the class $\{\mathfrak {Z}(\mathbb {S})\mid \mathbb {S}\in \mathcal {A}\}$ if it is bounded or $\infty $ otherwise.
We will focus on the study of the Zhou ordinal of the class $\mathcal {S}$ of separable LMPs. It is immediate that it is bounded by the cardinal successor of ${\left |\mathbb {R}\right |}$ .
Lemma 33. $\mathfrak {Z}(\mathcal {S})\leq (2^{\aleph _0})^+$ .
Proof. Every separable metrizable space S satisfies ${\left |S\right |}\leq 2^{\aleph _0}$ , and hence the bound follows from Theorem 30.
Next we provide the last technical ingredient for the constructions to be performed for our main Theorems 37 and 38. It a simple though essential device to enlarge a given LMP in such a way that the original structure is “isolated” and it does not produce any side effect on the enlargement.
Suppose that $\mathbb {T}=(T,\Sigma ,\{\tau _a\mid a\in L\})$ is an LMP with label set L. Let $e\notin T$ be a new state and let be an expansion of the label set by two new actions. Over the measurable space $(T^{\ast },\Sigma ^{\ast })\mathrel {\mathop :}= (T\oplus \{e\},\Sigma \oplus \{\{e\},\varnothing \})$ , we define a new LMP $\mathbb {T}^{\ast }$ with kernels given by
It is clear that $\mathbb {T}^{\ast }$ is an LMP. The kernel $\tau _{\triangledown }$ allows, with probability $1$ , a transition to e from each state $t\in T$ , and only loops around e.
The use of a new state and two extra kernels (instead of just a single new kernel) stems from the fact that in this way it is immediate that $\mathcal {R}^T$ (as a set operator) is the same, modulo e, for $\mathbb {T}$ and $\mathbb {T}^{\ast }$ . This has the following consequence, which will be used in the sequel.
Lemma 34. The Zhou ordinal is invariant under the map $\mathbb {T}\mapsto \mathbb {T}^{\ast }$ , namely: $\mathfrak {Z}(\mathbb {T}^{\ast }) =\mathfrak {Z}(\mathbb {T})$ .
The $\mathbb {T}\mapsto \mathbb {T}^{\ast }$ construction will be used in conjunction with the next lemma, where $\bar {S}$ is the intended enlargement that we referred to above.
Lemma 35. Let $\mathbb {S}=(S,\Sigma ,\{\tau _a\mid a\in L\})$ be an LMP and let $\mathbb {S'}=(S',\Sigma ',\{\tau ^{\prime }_a\mid a\in L\})$ be an LMP over a direct sum $(S',\Sigma ')=(S\oplus \bar {S},\Sigma \oplus \bar {\Sigma })$ such that $:$
-
• For all $r\in S$ and $a\in L$ , $\tau ^{\prime }_a(r,Q)=\tau _a(r,Q\cap S)$ .
-
• and .
-
• $S\in \Sigma ^{\prime }_0$ .
Then (equivalently, ) and hold for every $\alpha \geq 0$ .
Regarding the equation that involves $R^{\prime }_{\alpha }$ , it says that to know such relation it is enough to determine it in each direct summand separately. One interpretation of this is that whenever $S\in \Sigma ^{\prime }_0$ , no relevant information about $\mathbb {S}$ is lost in the direct sum.
The proofs of the main results of this section are based on further analysis of the LMP $\mathbb {U}$ from Example 6, which was the first example of a process with positive Zhou ordinal. Actually, $\mathfrak {Z}(\mathbb {U})=1$ as highlighted in Example 12.
A key idea behind the definition of $\mathbb {U}$ is that the non-measurable set V is essentially the only set that distinguishes $\mathfrak {m}_0$ from $\mathfrak {m}_1$ and hence s from t. This V can become “available” when all the rational intervals can be used to separate points in $I=(0,1)$ . From this approach one can control the unveiling of V using $B_n=(0,q_n)$ to become “available as tests” simultaneously or in parallel, and this is the reason why state bisimilarity is reached in one step in $\mathbb {U}$ . The same pattern will be used in Theorem 37. On the other hand a serial approach to the uncovering of the family $\{B_n\}$ will be followed in the proof of Theorem 38.
We will prove our first important result about $\mathfrak {Z}(\mathcal {S})$ , namely, that it is a limit ordinal. In order to do this we first give the construction of an LMP that will play an essential role in the aforementioned result. Since we will be exclusively concerned with the Zhou ordinal from now on, $\Sigma _0$ will always be the least stable $\sigma $ -algebra of the LMP in consideration and $R_0 \mathrel {\mathop :}= \mathcal {R}(\Sigma _0)$ .
Start with any $\mathbb {T}$ such that $\mathfrak {Z}(\mathbb {T})=\alpha +1$ . Consider the LMP $\mathbb {T}^{\ast }$ constructed in (1), that for simplicity we will denote by
. By Lemma 34, $\mathfrak {Z}(\mathbb {S})=\alpha +1$ . Let $z,y \in S\mathbin \smallsetminus\{e\}$ be such that $z \mathrel {R_{\alpha }} y$ but
. Then there exist $A_0\in \Sigma _{\alpha +1}\setminus \Sigma _{\alpha }$ and $n\in \omega $ such that $\tau _n(z,A_0)\neq \tau _n(y,A_0)$ . We now define a new process: Let
where
We will call $\Sigma '$ the $\sigma $ -algebra of $\mathbb {S}'$ and anything referred to this LMP will be primed: $\Sigma ^{\prime }_{\alpha }, R^{\prime }_{\alpha }, \sim ^{\prime }_s$ .
This new process will act as an amalgam of $\mathbb {S}$ and $\mathbb {U}$ with x replaced by S: Each state in I behaves either as z or y according to the label $m\in \omega $ , and the process continues inside $\mathbb {S}$ afterwards. Labels $\triangledown $ and allow to separate the LMP $\mathbb {S}$ from the rest in such a way that its behavior is independent of the enlargement. If that were not the case, event bisimilarity could identify states of S and $I\cup \{s,t\}$ , and therefore restrict the sets that appear in . Observe that $\mathbb {S}'$ will end up with infinitely many different kernels, even though $\mathbb {S}$ had only finitely many. Also note that for $r\in I$ , there are only three possible values of $\tau '(r,Q)$ : $\tau _n(z,Q\cap S)$ , $\tau _n(y,Q\cap S)$ or $0$ ; this is very similar to $\mathbb {U}$ , where there were only two possible values of $\tau _n(r,Q)$ .
Lemma 36. $\mathbb {S}'$ is an LMP. Moreover, and .
Proof. To show that $\mathbb {S}'$ is an LMP, we only need to check that $\tau ^{\prime }_a$ is a Markov kernel for every .
If $Q\in \Sigma '$ , measurability of $\tau ^{\prime }_m(\cdot ,Q)$ follows from the fact that $\tau _m(\cdot ,Q\cap S)$ is measurable for all $m\in \omega $ and from the measurability of the sets $(0,q_m)$ and $\{s,t\}$ . Measurability of $\tau ^{\prime }_{\Box }(\cdot ,Q)$ for only depends on the measurability of the characteristic functions involved. Finally, for fixed $r\in S'$ , all maps $\tau ^{\prime }_a(r,\cdot )$ are clearly subprobability measures.
For the second statement, consider the LMP obtained by adding the zero kernel with $\infty $ label to $\mathbb {S}$ . This operation does not modify $R_{\alpha }$ nor $\Sigma _{\alpha }$ . Moreover, it is immediate that for all $r\in S$ and labels a, $\tau ^{\prime }_a(r,Q)=\tau _a(r,Q\cap S)$ holds. Note that also $S\in \Sigma _0'$ , since . In this way, we may apply Lemma 35 to $\mathbb {S}$ and the measurable space $(I \oplus \{s,t\},\mathcal {B}_V\oplus \mathcal {P}(\{s,t\}))$ to obtain the result.
We are now ready to prove the previously announced result.
Theorem 37. $\mathfrak {Z}(\mathcal {S})$ is a limit ordinal.
Proof. First observe that $\mathfrak {Z}(\mathcal {S})>0$ as shown in [Reference Sánchez Terraf10]. Suppose by way of contradiction that $\mathfrak {Z}(\mathcal {S})=\alpha +1$ for some $\alpha \geq 0$ . Then there must exist a separable LMP $\mathbb {T}$ such that $\mathfrak {Z}(\mathbb {T})=\alpha +1$ . Now consider the LMP $\mathbb {S'}$ as in the previous construction. We show that $\mathfrak {Z}(\mathbb {S}')\geq \alpha +2$ . To see this it is enough to prove that $s\mathrel {R^{\prime }_{\alpha +1}}t$ but . For the first condition, let us show that . Let $Q\in \Sigma ^{\prime }_{\alpha +1}=\Sigma '(\mathcal {R}^T(\Sigma ^{\prime }_{\alpha }))$ and assume $Q\cap I \neq \varnothing $ ; we show that $Q\cap I =I $ . Let $r_0\in Q\cap I $ and $r\in I $ . Suppose that ; then there exist $m\in \omega $ and $B\in \Sigma ^{\prime }_{\alpha }$ such that $\tau ^{\prime }_m(r_0,B)\neq \tau ^{\prime }_m(r,B)$ , i.e., $\tau _m(z,B\cap S)\neq \tau _m(y,B\cap S)$ . By Lemma 36, $B\cap S\in \Sigma _{\alpha }$ , then ; but this is absurd since we chose $z,y$ in such a way they are indeed related. It follows that $r_0\mathrel {\mathcal {R}^T(\Sigma ^{\prime }_{\alpha })} r$ and since Q is $\mathcal {R}^T(\Sigma ^{\prime }_{\alpha })$ -closed, $r\in Q\cap I $ . Note that this yields . To show $(s,t) \in R^{\prime }_{\alpha +1}=\mathcal {R}^T(\Sigma ^{\prime }_{\alpha +1})$ , consider $\varnothing \neq Q\in \Sigma ^{\prime }_{\alpha +1}$ . By the previous calculation, $Q\cap I =I $ ; therefore $\tau ^{\prime }_{\infty }(s,Q)=1=\tau ^{\prime }_{\infty }(t,Q)$ . For the remaining labels we have $\tau ^{\prime }_a(s,Q)=0=\tau ^{\prime }_a(t,Q)$ .
We now show that . Recall that we had chosen $z,y$ and $A_0\in \Sigma _{\alpha +1}\setminus \Sigma _{\alpha }$ such that $\tau _n(z,A_0)\neq \tau _n(y,A_0)$ for some $n\in \omega $ . By Lemma 36, $A_0\in \Sigma ^{\prime }_{\alpha +1}$ and from this we conclude . We also observe that ; therefore . Then we have $V\in \Sigma ^{\prime }_{\alpha +2}$ and using that set with the transition labelled by $\infty $ we obtain .
It can be deduced from the proof of the previous theorem that from every separable process with Zhou ordinal $\alpha +1$ another one can be constructed with ordinal equal to $\alpha +2$ . In spite of this, this construction does not allow to construct a process with positive Zhou ordinal from one having null Zhou ordinal (i.e., having the Hennessy–Milner property).
In the next theorem, the cofinality $\operatorname {cf} (\lambda )$ of a limit ordinal $\lambda $ is the least order type (equivalently, the least cardinal) of an unbounded subset of $\lambda $ .
Theorem 38. $\operatorname {cf}(\mathfrak {Z}(\mathcal {S}))>\omega $ .
Proof. Towards a contradiction, suppose that for every $m\in \omega $ we have a separable $\mathbb {S}_m=(S^m,\Sigma ^m,\{\tau _n^m \}_{n\in \omega })$ with label set $\{(m,n)\mid n\in \omega \}$ such that $\zeta _m\mathrel {\mathop :}=\mathfrak {Z}(\mathbb {S}_m)$ satisfy $\sup _{m\in \omega }\zeta _m=\mathfrak {Z}(\mathcal {S})$ . We will assume that these LMPs have gone through the construction given in (1); this way each process now has two distinguished labels, which for ease of reference we call $(m,\triangledown )$ and , that allow them to be differentiated from each other with formulas.
We can assume $\zeta _0>0$ and also that $\{\zeta _m\}_{m\in \omega }$ is a strictly increasing sequence; for convenience, we set $\zeta _{-1}\mathrel {\mathop :}= 0$ . In this way $\zeta _{m-1}<\zeta _m$ for all $m\geq 0$ , and hence we can choose $x_m, y_m \in S^m$ such that $x_m \mathrel {R^m_{\zeta _{m-1}}} y_m$ but . Then there is a set $A_m \in \Sigma _{\zeta _m}^m\mathbin \smallsetminus \Sigma _{\zeta _{m-1}}^m$ such that for some $i\in \omega $ we have $\tau _i^m(x_m,A_m)\neq \tau _i^m(y_m,A_m)$ . By reordering the labels of the Markov kernels, we can assume that $i\in \omega $ is exactly m.
Let us define a new LMP with label set $L\mathrel {\mathop :}=\{(m,n)\mid m,n\in \omega \}\cup \{\infty \}$ :
where the kernels are given by
In this case the LMP $\mathbb {S}$ is an amalgam of the sum of all of the $\mathbb {S}^m$ and $\mathbb {U}$ . The sets $(0,q_n) = B_n$ will become available successively, using a serial approach to uncovering the non-measurable set V. In this way we can surpass the limit of the Zhou ordinals of the $\mathbb {S}^m$ .
We will call $(S,\Sigma )$ the measurable space of $\mathbb {S}$ . It is easy to see that this indeed defines an LMP and the separability of the base space follows from the separability of each of the countably many summands that make it up. We will show that $\mathfrak {Z}(\mathbb {S})\geq \mathfrak {Z}(\mathcal {S})+1$ , reaching a contradiction. For this, it is enough to verify that $(s,t)\in R_{\mathfrak {Z}(\mathcal {S})}\mathbin \smallsetminus R_{\mathfrak {Z}(\mathcal {S})+1}$ . This will be implied by the facts and $V \in \Sigma _{\mathfrak {Z}(\mathcal {S})+1}\mathbin \smallsetminus \Sigma _{\mathfrak {Z}(\mathcal {S})}$ which in turn are a consequence of the equality
for all $\eta \leq \mathfrak {Z}(\mathcal {S})$ , where $\Theta _{\eta }$ is the $\sigma $ -algebra on $I $ generated by the intervals $\{(0,q_m)\mid \zeta _m<\eta \}$ .
Before proving this, we notice that for each $m\in \omega $ , we can add to $\mathbb {S}^m$ zero kernels $\tau ^m_{\infty },\tau ^j_n \ (j\neq m)$ and get the property $\forall r\in S \ \forall a\in L \ \tilde {\tau }_a(r,Q)=\tau _a(r,Q\cap S)$ , while not changing $\Sigma ^m_{\eta }$ nor $R^m_{\eta }$ . Also, thanks to the distinguished labels $(m,\triangledown )$ and
(which cannot correspond to the label $(m,m)$ in $\mathbb {S}^m$ ), we have
. This way, all the hypotheses of Lemma 35 are satisfied. Then, for each $m\in \omega $ and $\eta $ we have
and
. Using the fact that there are countably many summands and also that $I,\{s,t\}\in \Sigma _0\subseteq \Sigma _{\eta }$ (because
), for all $\eta $ we can conclude
So all we have to do now is to show by induction on $\eta $ that
. If $\eta =0$ , then obviously $\Theta _0=\{\varnothing ,I \}$ , so we have to show that
is trivial. In order to do this, it is enough to show that $\{Q\in \Sigma _0\mid Q\cap I \in \{\varnothing ,I \}\}$ is stable. Assume that $Q\in \Sigma _0$ satisfies $ Q \cap I \in \{\varnothing ,I \}$ and $({\langle a \rangle _{>q}}Q) \cap I \neq \varnothing $ ; hence $a=(m,n)$ for some $m,n\in \omega $ (since it is obvious from the definition of $\tilde {\tau }_{\infty }$ that $a\neq \infty $ ). Then there is $r\in I $ such that $\tilde {\tau }^m_n(r, Q )>q$ . It follows that $m=n$ ; otherwise the kernel would equal zero.
From $ Q \in \Sigma _0$ we have $Q \cap S^m\in \Sigma ^m_0\subseteq \Sigma ^m_{\zeta _{m-1}}$ and considering $x_m \mathrel {R}_{\zeta _{m-1}} y_m$ , we conclude that $\tilde {\tau }^m_m(\cdot , Q)$ is constant on I. This yields $r'\in {\langle a \rangle _{>q}}Q$ for every $r'\in I$ . This shows that $\{Q\in \Sigma _0\mid Q\cap I \in \{\varnothing ,I \}\}$ is stable. As this class is easily seen to be a $\sigma $ -algebra, we have and therefore the result holds for $\eta =0$ .
Assume now that
. Notice that the kernels in $\mathbb {S}$ only depend on one, and only one, of the restrictions to $S^m$ and $I $ , and use this together with the IH to obtain
As $\mathcal {R}^T(\Theta _{\eta })= (S\mathbin \smallsetminus\{s,t\}\times S\mathbin \smallsetminus\{s,t\})\cup \{(s,t),(t,s)\}$ , then $R_{\eta }$ is the disjoint union
. Therefore, $A\subseteq I$ is $R_{\eta }$ -closed iff it is $\mathcal {R}^T(\bigoplus _{m\in \omega }\Sigma ^m_{\eta })$ -closed. Also, from the choice of $x_m,y_m$ we deduce that
. From this we have
For the limit case, assume
for all $\eta <\lambda $ . Then we have the following calculation:
This concludes the proof by induction of Equation (2) and thus ends the proof of the theorem.
Corollary 39. $\mathfrak {Z}(\mathcal {S})\geq \omega _1$ .
5 The example
In this section we construct, for each ordinal $\beta \leq \omega _1$ , an LMP $\mathbb {S}(\beta )$ such that for $\beta $ limit, $\mathfrak {Z}(\mathbb {S}(\beta ))= \beta $ . For this, we take the set $I \times \beta $ together with the product