Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-p2v8j Total loading time: 0.001 Render date: 2024-05-22T12:18:54.583Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Revelation and Reasons

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  02 February 2009

Extract

The article by Dr Farrer on ‘Revelation’ in the Faith and Logic collection is of special importance, for here we have a theologian attempting to steer between the Scylla of irrationalism and the Charybdis of apriorism. That is, by trying to point out the criteria for determining the truth of revelation he is able to avoid the extreme irrationalism that has characterised much Protestant theology in recent decades; while on the other hand, in concentrating attention upon these checks on religious truth he escapes that metaphysical assimilation of religious to deductive arguments which mars Thomism and (the more immediate cause of the irrationalist revolt) Hegelianism. Whereas the word ‘reason’ is a chameleon, which changes its colour in accordance with its environment, so that mathematical reasoning has a different style and rigour from reasoning in morals, and this in turn differs from scientific reasoning, etc., philosophers and theologians have tended to overlook such matters. A crude version of a common attitude can be expressed something as follows: ‘In religion there either is or is not a proper place for reasoning (and this will be deductive reasoning); if there is, we can divide theological assertions into two kinds, those which are provable by reason and those which are not; and if there is not, we must take religious assertions on faith.’ This attitude has two main evil effects.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © Scottish Journal of Theology Ltd 1958

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

page 352 note 1 Faith and Logic, ed. Mitchell, Basil (London, 1957), pp. 84107.Google Scholar

page 352 note 2 See especially op. cit., pp. 99–107.

page 353 note 1 op. cit., p. 99.

page 353 note 2 op. cit., pp. 96–99.

page 354 note 1 op. cit., p. 98.

page 355 note 1 I Cor. 2.9–15 quoted by Farrer, op. cit., p. 85.

page 355 note 2 Art. on ‘Examination of Theological Belief’, op. cit., p. 13.

page 356 note 1 op. cit., p. 102.

page 357 note 1 op. tit., p. 98.

page 358 note 1 Though there are considerable difficulties in the notion of perfect goodness in this context, as is well brought out by Martin, C. B. in his article ‘The Perfect Good’ reprinted in New Essays in Philosophical Theology, ed. Flew, and Macintyre, , (London, 1955), pp. 212ffGoogle Scholar.

page 359 note 1 op. cit., p. 106.