Hostname: page-component-8448b6f56d-c47g7 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-16T22:20:47.840Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Thinking as a Team: Towards an Explanation of Nonselfish Behavior*

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  18 June 2009

Robert Sugden
Affiliation:
Economics, University of East Anglia

Extract

For most of the problems that economists consider, the assumption that agents are self-interested works well enough, generating predictions that are broadly consistent with observation. In some significant cases, however, we find economic behavior that seems to be inconsistent with self-interest. In particular, we find that some public goods and some charitable ventures are financed by the independent voluntary contributions of many thousands of individuals. In Britain, for example, the lifeboat service is entirely financed by voluntary contributions. In all rich countries, charitable appeals raise large amounts of money for famine relief in the Third World. The willingness of individuals to contribute to such projects is an economic fact that requires an explanation.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © Social Philosophy and Policy Foundation 1993

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 See, for example, Sugden, Robert, “Consistent Conjectures and Voluntary Contributions to Public Goods: Why the Conventional Theory Does Not Work,” Journal of Public Economics, vol. 27 (1984), pp. 117–24CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Andreoni, James, “Privately Provided Public Goods in a Large Economy: The Limits of Altruism,” Journal of Public Economics, vol. 35 (1988), pp. 5773CrossRefGoogle Scholar; and Covven, Tyler, “Altruism and the Argument from Offsetting Transfers,” in this volume.Google Scholar

2 I present this argument, and summarize the econometric evidence, in Sugden, Robert, “On the Economics of Philanthropy,” Economic Journal, vol. 92 (1982), pp. 341–50.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

3 Andreoni, James, “Impure Altruism and Donations to Public Goods: A Theory of Warm-Glow Giving,” Economic Journal, vol. 100 (1990), pp. 464–77.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

4 Olson, Mancur, Tiie Logic of Collective Action (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1965), p. 60Google Scholar; Becker, Gary S., “A Theory of Social Interactions,” Journal of Political Economy, vol. 82 (1974), p. 1083.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

5 For example, Regan, Donald, Utilitarianism and Cooperation (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1980)CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Sugden, Robert, “Reciprocity: The Supply of Public Goods through Voluntary Contributions,” Economic Journal, vol. 94 (1984), pp. 772–87.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

6 The argument I present here is similar to those of Hodgson, D. H., Consequences of Utilitarianism (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1967)Google Scholar; and Regan, , Utilitarianism and Cooperation.Google Scholar

7 Sugden, Robert, The Economics of Rights, Co-operation, and Welfare (Oxford: Basil Black-well, 1986).Google Scholar

8 To see why, let p be the probability that B will stay silent. Then if A stays silent, A's expected utility is –10(1 – p). If A confesses, A's expected utility is – 10p – (1 – p). The former expected utility is greater than the latter if p is greater than 9/19.

9 This feature is brought out by Hodgson, who considers a game similar to the Prisoners' Coordination Problem (see his Consequences of Utilitarianism). Hodgson's game is played by two act utilitarians, each of whom seeks to maximize the sum of all persons' utilities. Hodgson argues that act-utilitarian players would have no reason to cooperate. Regan discusses the same game and reaches a similar conclusion in his Utilitarianism and Cooperation.

10 Schelling, Thomas, The Strategy of Conflict (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1960), especially pp. 5458.Google Scholar

11 These are among the findings of some experimental work I have done with Judith Mehta and Chris Starmer, which has not yet been published.

12 Lewis, David, Convention: A Philosophical Study (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1969), pp. 3536.Google Scholar

13 Keynes, John Maynard, The General Theory of Employment, Interest, and Money (London: Macmillan, 1936), p. 156.Google Scholar

14 Strictly speaking, Keynes's competition is not a coordination game, since it is zerosum (the object is to beat the other competitors). However, the first sentence in the quotation from Keynes could apply equally well to a coordination game, and this may be what Schelling has in mind.

15 Schelling, , Strategy of Conflict, p. 94Google Scholar

16 This was part of the experimental work referred to in footnote 11.

17 Gauthier, David, “Coordination,” Dialogue, vol. 14 (1975), pp. 195221CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Bacharach, Michael, “Games with Context-Sensitive Strategy Spaces,” paper presented at International Conference on Game Theory, Florence, 06 1991.Google Scholar

18 Gauthier's Principle of Coordination is, in fact, slightly stronger than the principle I have just attributed to him. Gauthier's principle states that if an outcome is (i) a Nash equilibrium, (iii) Parelo optimal, and (iii) strictly Pareto preferred to all other Nash equilibria, then it is rational for each player to choose the strategy that allows this outcome to be brought about. (A Nash equilibrium is a combination of strategies, one for each player, such that each player's strategy is optimal for him, given the strategies of the others. One outcome is strictly Pareto preferred to another if all players prefer the former to the latter. An outcome x is Pareto optimal if there exists no feasible outcome y such that at least one player prefers y to x, and no player prefers x to y.) Since any outcome which is strictly Pareto preferred to all other outcomes must be a Nash equilibrium, Gauthier's Principle of Coordination implies the principle I have attributed to him.

19 Gauthier, , “Coordination,” p. 200.Google Scholar

20 Ibid., p. 196. In later work, Gauthier has developed a theory of “constrained maximization” which implies, among other things, that (in certain circumstances) it is rational to cooperate in the Prisoner's Dilemma; see Gauthier, David, Morals by Agreement (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1986).Google Scholar A somewhat similar conception of rationality is proposed by McClennen, Edward F. in Rationality and Dynamic Choice (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1990).CrossRefGoogle Scholar it is possible that the Principle of Coordination is a valid implication of this kind of theory.

21 A similar criticism is made by Gilbert, Margaret in “Rationality and Salience,” Philosophical Studies, vol. 57 (1989), pp. 6177.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

22 Hurley, Susan L., Natural Reasons (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1989), p. 148.Google Scholar

23 In contrast, Hurley (ibid., pp. 136–70) argues that, in games like the Prisoners' Coordination Problem, it is irrational for the players not to think as a team or, as she puts it, it is irrational for them not to participate in “collective agency.” Her argument is that the unit of agency should itself be a matter of rational choice; if “it is a good thing for such collective agency to exist,” then it is rational to participate in collective agency, and irrational not to (p. 157). I am inclined to think that the idea of rational choice is not meaningful until the unit of agency has been specified.