Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-76fb5796d-wq484 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-29T04:24:08.867Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Bibliography

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  21 July 2009

J. David Velleman
Affiliation:
New York University
Get access

Summary

Image of the first page of this content. For PDF version, please use the ‘Save PDF’ preceeding this image.'
Type
Chapter
Information
Self to Self
Selected Essays
, pp. 361 - 378
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2005

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Allison, Henry E., Kant's Theory of Freedom (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1990)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Anderson, Elizabeth, Value in Ethics and Economics (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1993)Google Scholar
Andrews, John D. W., The Active Self in Psychotherapy: An Integration of Therapeutic Styles (Boston: Allyn & Bacon, 1991)Google Scholar
Annas, Julia, “Personal Love and Kantian Ethics in Effi Briest,” in Friendship: A Philosophical Reader, ed. Neera Kapur Badhwar (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1993), 155–73Google Scholar
Anscombe, Elizabeth, “The First Person,” in her Metaphysics and the Philosophy of Mind: Collected Papers (Oxford: Blackwell, 1981), 21–36Google Scholar
Anscombe, Elizabeth, Intention (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1957); reprinted (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2000)Google Scholar
Anscombe, Roderick, “The Myth of the True Self,”Psychiatry 52 (1989): 209–17CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Aristotle, Nichomachean Ethics.
Aronson, E., “Dissonance theory: Progress and problems,” in Theories of Cognitive Consistency: A Sourcebook, ed. Robert P. Ableson, Elliot Aronson, William J. McGuire, Theodore M. Newcomb, Milton J. Rosenberg, and Percy H. Tannenbaum (Chicago: Rand McNally, 1968), 5–27Google Scholar
Aronson, E., “The Theory of Cognitive Dissonance: a Current Perspective, Advances in Experimental Social Psychology 4 (1969): 1–34CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Aronson, E., “The Return of the Repressed: Dissonance Theory Makes a Comeback,”Psychological Inquiry 3 (1992): 303–311CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Aronson, E., and Carlsmith, J. M., “Performance expectancy as a determinant of actual performance,”Journal of Abnormal and Social Psychology 65 (1962): 178–82CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Arpaly, Nomy, and Schroeder, Timothy, “Alienation and Externality,”Canadian Journal of Philosophy 29 (1999): 371–387Google Scholar
Augustine, St., The City of God, transl. Marcus Dods (New York: The Modern Library, 1950)Google Scholar
Aune, Bruce, “Speaking of Selves,”Philosophical Quarterly 44 (1994): 279–93CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Badhwar, Neera Kapur, “Friends as Ends in Themselves,”Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 48 (1987): 1–25CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Badhwar, Neera Kapur (listed as Kapur, Neera Badhwar), “Why It Is Wrong to Be Always Guided by the Best: Consequentialism and Friendship,”Ethics 101 (1991): 483–504Google Scholar
Baier, Annette, “The Moral Perils of Intimacy,” in Pragmatism's Freud: The Moral Disposition of Psychoanalysis, ed. Joseph H. Smith and William Kerrigan (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1986), 93–101Google Scholar
Baron, Marcia, “On Admirable Immorality,”Ethics 96 (1986): 557–66CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Baron, Marcia, “Impartiality and Friendship,”Ethics 101 (1991): 836–57CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Baron, Marcia, Kantian Ethics Almost without Apology (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1995)Google Scholar
Baumann, Paul, and Betzler, Monika (eds.), Practical Conflicts: New Philosophical Essays (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2004)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bem, D. J., “Self-perception theory,” in Advances in Experimental Social Psychology, Vol. 6, ed. Leonard Berkowitz (New York: Academic Press, 1972), 1–62Google Scholar
Benhabib, Seyla, “The Generalized and the Concrete Other: The Kohlberg-Gilligan Controversy and Moral Theory,” in Women and Moral Theory, ed. Eva Feder Kittay and Diana T. Meyers (Totowa, NJ: Rowman and Littlefield, 1987), 154–177Google Scholar
Berkowitz, L., “Mood, self-awareness, and willingness to help,”Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 52 (1987): 721–29CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Berkowitz, L., & Turner, C., “Perceived anger level, instigating agent, and aggression,” in Cognitive Alteration of Feeling States, ed. H. London and R. E. Nisbett (Chicago: Aldine, 1974), 174–89Google Scholar
Bermúdez, José Luis, The Paradox of Self-Consciousness (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1998)Google Scholar
Bettelheim, Bruno, Freud and Man's Soul (New York: Vintage, 1984)Google Scholar
Blackburn, Simon, “Has Kant Refuted Parfit?” in Reading Parfit, ed. Jonathan Dancy (Oxford: Blackwell, 1997) 180–202Google Scholar
Blackburn, Simon, Ruling Passions (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1998)Google Scholar
Blum, Lawrence A., Friendship, Altruism and Morality (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1980)Google Scholar
Blum, Lawrence, “Iris Murdoch and the Domain of the Moral,”Philosophical Studies 50 (1986): 343–67CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Boër, Stephen E., and Lycan, William G., Knowing Who (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1986)Google Scholar
Borch-Jacobsen, Mikkel, The Freudian Subject, transl. Catherine Porter (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1988)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brakel, Linda, “Phantasy and Wish: A Proper Function Account for Human A-Rational Primary Process Mediated Mentation,”Australasian Journal of Philosophy 80 (2002): 1–16CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Branden, Nathaniel, “Love and Psychological Visibility,” in Friendship: A Philosophical Reader, ed. Neera Kapur Badhwar (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1993), 64–72Google Scholar
Bratman, Michael, Intention, Plans, and Practical Reason (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1987)Google Scholar
Bratman, Michael, “Identification, Decision, and Treating as a Reason,” in his Faces of Intention (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999), 185–206CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bratman, Michael, “Reflection, Planning, and Temporally Extended Agency,”Philosophical Review 109 (2000): 35–61CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brewer, Bill, “Self-Location and Agency,”Mind 101 (1992): 17–34CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brodt, S. E., and Zimbardo, P. G., “Modifying shyness-related social behavior through symptom misattribution,”Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 41 (1981): 437–49CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Buss, Sarah, and Overton, Lee (eds.) Contours of Agency: Essays on Themes from Harry Frankfurt (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 2002)Google Scholar
Calhoun, Cheshire, “An Apology for Moral Shame” (forthcoming in the Journal of Political Philosophy)
Campbell, John, “The Reductionist View of the Self,” in Reduction, Explanation, and Realism, ed. David Charles and Kathleen Lennon, (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1992), 380–419Google Scholar
Campbell, John, “Self-Reference and Self-Knowledge,” in Past, Space, and Self (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1994), Chapter 4Google Scholar
Cantor, J. R., Zillman, D., and Bryant, J., “Enhancement of experienced sexual arousal in response to erotic stimuli through misattribution of unrelated residual excitation,”Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 32 (1975): 69–75CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cavell, Marcia, “Knowing and Valuing: Some Questions of Genealogy,” in Psychoanalysis, Mind and Art: Perspectives on Richard Wollheim, ed. Jim Hopkins and Anthony Saville (Oxford: Blackwell, 1992), 68–86Google Scholar
Cavell, Stanley, “The Avoidance of Love: A Reading of King Lear,” in his Must We Mean What We Say? A Book of Essays (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1976), 267–353Google Scholar
Cohen, G. A., “Reason, Humanity, and the Moral Law,” in The Sources of Normativity, ed. Onora O'Neill (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996) 167–70Google Scholar
Coltart, Nina, “Attention,” in her Slouching towards Bethlehem (New York: Guildford, 1992), 176–93Google Scholar
Conly, Sarah, “The Objectivity of Morals and the Subjectivity of Agents,”American Philosophical Quarterly 22 (1985): 275–86Google Scholar
Conly, Sarah, “Utilitarianism and Integrity,”Monist 66 (1983): 298–311CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cooper, J., Zanna, M. P., and Taves, P. A., “Arousal as a necessary condition for attitude change following induced compliance,”Journal of Personality & Social Psychology 36 (1978): 1101–1106CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Copp, David, “Korsgaard on Normativity, Identity, and the Ground of Obligation,” in Rationality, Realism, Revision: Proceedings of the Third International Congress of the Society for Analytical Philosophy, vol. 23 of Perspektiven der Analytischen Philosophie, ed. Julian Nida-Rümelin (Berlin: de Gruyter, 1999), 572–581Google Scholar
Cottingham, John, “Ethics and Impartiality,”Philosophical Studies 43 (1983): 83–99CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cross, S. E., and Markus, H. R., “The Willful Self,”Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin 16 (1990): 726–42CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Darwall, Stephen L., “Two Kinds of Respect,”Ethics 88 (1977): 36–49CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Darwall, Stephen L., The British Moralists and the Internal ‘Ought’ 1640–1740 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1995), Chapter 9CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Darwall, Stephen L., “Self-Interest and Self-Concern,”Social Philosophy and Policy 14 (1997): 158–78CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Darwall, Stephen L., “Empathy, Sympathy, Care,”Philosophical Studies 89 (1998): 261–82CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Davidson, D., Essays on Actions and Events (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1980)Google Scholar
Deci, E. L., and Ryan, R. M., “A motivational approach to self: Integration in Personality,” Perspectives on Motivation, Nebraska Symposium on Motivation 1990, ed. Richard Dienstbier (Lincoln: University of Nebraska Press, 1991), 237–88Google Scholar
Deigh, John, “Shame and Self-Esteem: A Critique,”Ethics 93 (1983): 225–45CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Deigh, John, “Freud, Naturalism, and Modern Moral Philosophy,” in his The Sources of Moral Agency: Essays in Moral Psychology and Freudian Theory (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996a), Chapter 6CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Deigh, John, “Remarks on Some Difficulties in Freud's Theory of Moral Development,” in his The Sources of Moral Agency: Essays in Moral Psychology and Freudian Theory (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996b), Chapter 4CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Delaney, Neil, “Romantic Love and Loving Commitment: Articulating a Modern Ideal,”American Philosophical Quarterly 33 (1996): 339–56Google Scholar
Dennett, Daniel, “Where Am I?” in his Brainstorms: Philosophical Essays on Mind and Psychology (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1981), 310–23Google Scholar
Dennett, Daniel, “The Origins of Selves,”Cogito 3 (1989): 163–73CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dennett, Daniel, “The Reality of Selves,” in his Consciousness Explained (Boston: Little, Brown and Company, 1991), Chapter 13Google Scholar
Dennett, Daniel, “The Self as a Center of Narrative Gravity,” in Self and Consciousness: Multiple Perspectives, ed. Frank S. Kessel, Pamela M. Cole, and Dale L. Johnson (Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum Associates, 1992) 103–115Google Scholar
Dennett, Daniel, with Humphrey, Nicholas, “Speaking for Our Selves,” in his Brainchildren: Essays on Designing Minds (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1998), 31–58Google Scholar
Dent, N. J. H., “Duty and Inclination,”Mind 83 (1974): 552–70CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dillon, Robin S., “Respect and Care: Toward Moral Integration,”Canadian Journal of Philosophy 22 (1992a): 105–32CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dillon, Robin S., “Toward a Feminist Conception of Self-Respect,”Hypatia 7 (1992b): 52–69CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dipboye, R. L., “A critical review of Korman's self-consistency theory of work motivation and occupational choice,”Organizational Behavior and Human Performance 18 (1977): 108–26CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Downie, R. S., and Telfer, Elizabeth, Respect for Persons (New York: Shocken, 1970)Google Scholar
Seuss, Dr., Horton Hears a Who! (New York: Random House, 1954)Google Scholar
Seuss, Dr., Happy Birthday to You! (New York: Random House, 1959)Google Scholar
Eagle, Morris, “Psychoanalysis and the Personal,” in Mind, Psychoanalysis and Science, ed. P. Clark and C. Wright (Oxford: Blackwell, 1988), 91–111Google Scholar
Eagle, Morris, “Psychoanalytic Conceptions of the Self,” in The Self: Interdisciplinary Approaches, ed. J. Strauss and G. R. Goethals (New York: Springer-Verlag, 1991), 49–65Google Scholar
Eisenberg, N., Cialdini, R. B., McCreath, H., and Shell, R., “Consistency-based compliance: When and why do children become vulnerable?”Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 52 (1987): 1174–81CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Eisenberg, N., Cialdini, R. B., McCreath, H., and Shell, R., “Consistency-based compliance in children: When and why do consistency procedures have immediate effects?”International Journal of Behavioural Development 12 (1989): 351–67CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Eliot, George, Felix Holt (London: Penguin, 1995)Google Scholar
Elliot, A. J., and Devine, P. G., “On the motivational nature of cognitive dissonance: Dissonance as psychological discomfort,”Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 67 (1994): 382–94CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ellison, Ralph, Invisible Man (New York: New American Library, 1952)Google Scholar
Elster, Jon, Strong Feelings: Emotion, Addiction, and Human Behavior (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1999)Google Scholar
Epstein, Mark, Thoughts Without a Thinker: Psychotherapy From a Buddhist Perspective (New York: Basic Books, 1995)Google Scholar
Epstein, S., “The Self-Concept Revisited; Or a Theory of a Theory,”American Psychologist 28 (1973): 404–416CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Epstein, S., “The Unity Principle Versus the Reality and Pleasure Principles, Or the Tale of the Scorpion and the Frog,” in Self-Concept: Advances in Theory and Research, ed. M. D. Lynch, A. A. Norem-Hebeisen, and K. J. Gergen (Cambridge, MA: Ballinger, 1981)Google Scholar
Erikson, Erik, Identity, Youth, and Crisis (New York: W. W. Norton, 1968), 74–90Google Scholar
Evans, Gareth, The Varieties of Reference (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1982)Google Scholar
Fairbairn, W. R. D., Psychoanalytic Studies of the Personality (London: Routledge, 1990)Google Scholar
Fazio, R. H., Zanna, M. P., and Cooper, J., “Dissonance and self-perception: An integrative view of each theory's proper domain of application,”Journal of Experimental Social Psychology 13 (1977): 464–479CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Festinger, L., and Carlsmith, J. M., “Cognitive Consequences of Forced Compliance,”Journal of Abnormal and Social Psychology 58 (1959), 203–11CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Flanagan, Owen, “Multiple Identity, Character Transformation, and Self-Reclamation,” in Philosophical Psychopathology, eds. G. Graham and Lynn Stephens, (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1994), Chapter 7; reprinted in his Self Expressions (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1996), 65–87Google Scholar
Foot, Philippa, “Are Moral Considerations Overriding?” in her Virtues and Vices (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1978a), 181–88Google Scholar
Foot, Philippa, “Morality as a System of Hypothetical Imperatives,” in her Virtues and Vices (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1978b), 157–73Google Scholar
Frankena, William K., “The Ethics of Respect for Persons,”Philosophical Topics 14 (1986): 149–67CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Frankfurt, Harry, “Identification and Wholeheartedness,” in his The Importance of What We Care About (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1988a), Chapter 12CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Frankfurt, Harry, “Rationality and the Unthinkable,” in his The Importance of What We Care About (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1988b), Chapter 13CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Frankfurt, Harry, The Importance of What We Care About (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1988c)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Frankfurt, Harry, “Autonomy, Necessity, and Love,” in Vernunftbegriffe in der Moderne, ed. Hans Friedrich Fulda and Rolf-Peter Horstmann (Klett-Cotta, 1994), 433–47; reprinted in his Necessity, Volition, and Love (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1999)Google Scholar
Frankfurt, Harry, “Some Thoughts about Caring,”Ethical Perspectives 5 (1998): 3–14CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Frankfurt, Harry, “On the Necessity of Ideals,” in his Necessity, Volition, and Love (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999a), Chapter 9Google Scholar
Frankfurt, Harry, “The Faintest Passion,” in his Necessity, Volition, and Love (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999b), Chapter 8Google Scholar
Frankfurt, Harry, Necessity, Volition, and Love (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999c)Google Scholar
Freedman, J. L., and Fraser, S. C., “Compliance without pressure: The foot-in-the-door technique,” Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 4 (1966): 195–202Google Scholar
Freud, Anna, The Ego and the Mechanisms of Defense (London: Hogarth Press, 1937), 109–121; reprinted in Pivotal Papers on Identification, ed. George H. Pollock (Madison, CT: International Universities Press, 1993), 105–14Google Scholar
Freud, Sigmund, “Group Psychology and the Analysis of the Ego,” in S. E., vol. 18, 67–143
Freud, Sigmund, “Instincts and Their Vicissitudes,” in S. E., vol. 14, 111–40
Freud, Sigmund, “Notes Upon a Case of Obsessional Neurosis,” in S. E., vol. 10, 153–249
Freud, Sigmund, “Observations on Transference-Love,” in S. E., vol. 12, 157–71
Freud, Sigmund, “On Narcissism: An Introduction,” in S. E., vol. 14, 67–102
Freud, Sigmund, “Psycho-Analysis,” in S. E., vol. 20, 261–70
Freud, Sigmund, “Recommendations to Physicians Practicing Psycho-Analysis,” in S. E., vol. 12, 111–20
Freud, Sigmund, “The Economic Problem of Masochism,” in S. E., vol. 19, 156–70
Freud, Sigmund, “The Libido Theory,” in S. E., vol. 18, 255–59
Freud, Sigmund, “Three Essays on the Theory of Sexuality,” in S. E., vol. 7, 125–243
Freud, Sigmund, An Autobiographical Study, in S. E., vol. 20, 3–74
Freud, Sigmund, Civilization and Its Discontents, S. E., vol. 21, 59–145
Freud, Sigmund, Five Lectures on Psychoanalysis, in S. E., vol. 11, 3–55
Freud, Sigmund, Group Psychology, in S. E., vol. 18, 69–143
Freud, Sigmund, Inhibitions, Symptoms and Anxiety, in S. E., vol. 20, 77–175
Freud, Sigmund, Introductory Lectures on Psychoanalysis, in S. E., vol. 16
Freud, Sigmund, Moses and Monotheism, in S. E., vol. 23, 3–137
Freud, Sigmund, New Introductory Lectures in Psychoanalysis, in S. E., vol. 22, 3–182
Freud, Sigmund, Outline of Psychoanalysis, in S. E., vol. 23, 141–207
Freud, Sigmund, The Ego and the Id, in S. E., vol. 19, 3–66CrossRef
Freud, Sigmund, The Standard Edition of the Complete Psychological Works of Sigmund Freud, ed. James Strachey et al. (London: Hogarth Press and the Institute of Psycho-Analysis, 1953–1974)Google Scholar
Freud, Sigmund, Totem and Taboo, in S. E., vol. 13, ix–162
Gewirth, Alan, “Ethical Universalism and Particularism,”Journal of Philosophy 85 (1988): 283–302CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gibbard, Allan, Wise Choices, Apt Feelings: A Theory of Normative Judgment (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1990)Google Scholar
Gilbert, Margaret, On Social Facts (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1992)Google Scholar
Goldman, M., Seever, M., and Seever, M., “Social labeling and the foot-in-the-door effect,”The Journal of Social Psychology 117 (1982): 19–23CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gorasini, D. R., and Olson, J. M., “Does self-perception change explain the foot-in-the-door effect?”Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 69 (1995): 91–105CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Green, O. H., The Emotions: A Philosophical Theory (Boston: Kluwer, 1992)Google Scholar
Green, O. H., “Is Love an Emotion?” Love Analyzed, ed. Roger E. Lamb (Boulder, CO.: Westview, 1997) 209–24Google Scholar
Greenspan, Patricia, Emotions and Reason: An Inquiry into Emotional Justification (New York: Routledge, 1988)Google Scholar
Greenwald, A. G., Carnot, C. G., Beach, R., and Young, B., “Increasing Voting Behavior by Asking People if They Expect to Vote,”Journal of Applied Psychology 72 (1987): 315–18CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Grusec, J. E., and Redler, E., “Attribution, reinforcement, and altruism: A developmental analysis,”Developmental Psychology 16 (1980): 525–34CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Guyer, Paul, “The Possibility of the Categorical Imperative,”Philosophical Review 104 (1995): 353–85CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hamilton, Andy, “A New Look at Personal Identity,”The Philosophical Quarterly 45 (1995): 332–49CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hardcastle, Valerie Gray, and Flanagan, Owen, “Multiplex vs. Multiple Selves: Distinguishing Dissociative Disorders,”The Monist 82 (1999): 645–57CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Harman, Gilbert, Change in View: Principles of Reasoning (Cambridge, MA: Bradford Books, 1986)Google Scholar
Harmon-Jones, E., and Mills, J. (eds.), Cognitive Dissonance: Progress on a Pivotal Theory in Social Psychology (Washington, DC: American Psychological Association, 1999)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Harré, Rom, Social Being (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1979)Google Scholar
Harré, Rom, The Singular Self: An Introduction to the Psychology of Personhood (London: Sage Publications, 1998)Google Scholar
Hatzimoysis, Anthony (ed.), Philosophy and the Emotions (New York: Cambridge University Press, 2003)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hawthorne, Nathaniel, The Scarlet Letter (New York: Bantam Books, 1986)Google Scholar
Herman, Barbara, The Practice of Moral Judgement (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1993)Google Scholar
Higgins, E. T., Rhodewalt, F., and Zanna, M. P., “Dissonance motivation: Its nature, persistence, and reinstatement,”Journal of Experimental Social Psychology 15 (1979): 16–34CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hill, Thomas E. Jr., “Humanity as an End in Itself,” in his Dignity and Practical Reason in Kant's Moral Theory (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1992), 38–57Google Scholar
Hollis, Martin, Models of Man (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1977)Google Scholar
Hussain, Nadeem, “The Guise of A Reason,” 121(2004) Philosophical Studies: 263–75CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ishiguro, Hidé, “Imagination II,”Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society Supp. Vol. 41 (1967): 37–56Google Scholar
Jackson, Frank, “Decision-Theoretic Consequentialism and the Nearest and Dearest Objection,”Ethics 101 (1991): 461–82CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jensen, R. E., and Moore, S. G., “The effect of attribute statements on cooperativeness and competitiveness in school-age boys,”Child Development 48 (1977): 305–07CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jeske, Diane, “Friendship, Virtue, and Impartiality,”Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 57 (1997): 51–72CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Johnson, Edward, “Ignoring Persons,” in Respect for Persons, ed. O. H. Green, Tulane Studies in Philosophy 31 (1982): 91–105Google Scholar
Jones, David H., “Freud's Theory of Moral Conscience,”Philosophy 41 (1966): 34–57CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jussim, L., Eccles, J., and Madon, S., “Social perception, social stereotypes, and teacher expectations: Accuracy and the quest for the powerful self-fulfilling prophecy,” in Advances in Experimental Social Psychology, Vol. 28, ed. M. P. Zanna (New York: Academic Press, 1996), 281–388Google Scholar
Jussim, L., Yen, H. J., and Aiello, J. R., “Self-consistency, self-enhancement, and accuracy in reactions to feedback,”Journal of Experimental and Social Psychology 31 (1995): 322–56CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kant, Immanuel, Critique of Practical Reason, transl. Lewis White Beck (Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill, 1956)Google Scholar
Kant, Immanuel, Groundwork of the Metaphysic of Morals, transl. H. J. Paton (New York: Harper and Row, 1964)Google Scholar
Kant, Immanuel, Critique of Pure Reason, transl. Norman Kemp Smith (New York: St. Martin's Press, 1965)Google Scholar
Kant, Immmanuel, “On the Proverb: That May be True in Theory, But Is of No Practical Use,” in Perpetual Peace and Other Essays, transl. Ted Humphrey (Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing, 1983), 61–92Google Scholar
Kant, Immanuel, The Metaphysics of Morals, transl. Mary Gregor (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kant, Immanuel, Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals, transl. Mary Gregor (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1997)Google Scholar
Kavka, Gregory, “The Toxin Puzzle,”Analysis 43 (1983): 33–36CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kekes, John, “Morality and Impartiality,”American Philosophical Quarterly 18 (1981): 295–303Google Scholar
Kelley, H. H., “Attribution theory in social psychology,” in Nebraska Symposium on Motivation, 1967, Vol. 15 of Current Theory and Research in Motivation, ed. David Levine (Lincoln: University of Nebraska Press, 1967), 192–238Google Scholar
Kihlstrom, J. F., and Cantor, N., “Mental Representations of the Self,” in Advances in Experimental and Social Psychology, ed. L. Berkowitz (New York: Academic Press, 1984), vol. 17, 2–40Google Scholar
Korman, A. K., “Toward an Hypothesis of Work Behavior,” 54 Journal of Applied Psychology 54 (1970): 31–41CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Korsgaard, Christine, “Skepticism about Practical Reason,”Journal of Philosophy 83 (1986): 5–25CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Korsgaard, Christine, “An Introduction to the Ethical, Political, and Religious Thought of Kant,” in her Creating the Kingdom of Ends (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996a), 3–42CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Korsgaard, Christine, “Kant's Analysis of Obligation: the Argument of Groundwork I,” in her Creating the Kingdom of Ends (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996b), 43–76CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Korsgaard, Christine, “Kant's Formula of Universal Law,” in her Creating the Kingdom of Ends (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996c), 77–105CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Korsgaard, Christine, (with Cohen, G. A., Raymond Geuss, , Thomas Nagel, , and Bernard Williams, ), The Sources of Normativity, ed. Onora O'Neill. (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996d)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Korsgaard, Christine, “The Normativity of Instrumental Reason, in Ethics and Practical Reason, ed. Garrett Cullity & Berys Gaut (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1997), 213–54Google Scholar
Korsgaard, Christine, “Self-Constitution in the Ethics of Plato and Kant,”Journal of Ethics 3 (1999): 1–29CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kraut, R. E., “Effects of social labeling on giving to charity,”Journal of Experimental Social Psychology (1973): 551–62CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kraut, Robert, “Love De Re,”Midwest Studies in Philosophy 10 (1986): 413–30CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lamb, Roger E., “Love and Rationality,” in Love Analyzed, ed. Roger E. Lamb (Boulder, CO: Westview, 1997), 23–47Google Scholar
Lampl-de Groot, Jeanne, “Ego Ideal and Superego,”The Psychoanalytic Study of the Child 17 (1962): 94–106CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lecky, P., Self-Consistency: A Theory of Personality (New York: Island Press, 1945)Google Scholar
Levine, Frederic J., and Kravis, Robert, “Psychoanalytic Theories of the Self: Contrasting Clinical Approaches to the New Narcissism,” in The Book of the Self: Person, Pretext, and Process, ed. Polly Young-Eisendrath and James A. Hall (New York: New York University Press, 1987), 306–330Google Scholar
Lewis, David, “Attitudes De Dicto and De Se,”The Philosophical Review 88 (1979): 513–14CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Locke, John, An Essay Concerning Human Understanding, ed. Peter H. Nidditch (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1975)Google Scholar
Lyons, William G., Emotion (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1980)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lycan, William G., Consciousness (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1987)Google Scholar
Mackie, John, “The Transcendental ‘I’,” in Philosophical Subjects: Essays Presented to P. F. Strawson, ed. Zak van Straaten (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1980), 48–61Google Scholar
Madell, Geoffrey, “Personal Identity and the Idea of a Human Being,” in Human Beings, ed. David Cockburn (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991), 127–42Google Scholar
Malcolm, Janet, Psychoanalysis: The Impossible Profession (New York: Vintage Press, 1980)Google Scholar
Maracek, J., & Mettee, D. R., “Avoidance of continued success as a function of self-esteem, level of esteem certainty, and responsibility for success,”Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 22 (1972): 98–107CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Martin, Raymond, “Having the Experience: The Next Best Thing to Being There,”Philosophical Studies 70 (1993): 305–21CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mason, Michelle, Moral Virtue and Reasons for Action, (Ph.D. diss.: University of Chicago, 2001)Google Scholar
McFall, Lynne, “Integrity,”Ethics 98 (1987): 5–20CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McNulty, S. E., and Swann, W. B. Jr., “Psychotherapy, Self-Concept Change, and Self-Verification,” in The Relational Self: Theoretical Convergences in Psychoanalysis and Social Psychology, ed. Rebecca C. Curtis (New York: Guildford Press, 1991), 213–37Google Scholar
Mellor, D. H., “I and Now,” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 89 (1989): 79–94; reprinted in his Matters of Metaphysics (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991)Google Scholar
Mezzacappa, E. S., Katkin, E. S., and Palmer, S. N., “Epinephrine, arousal, and emotion: A new look at two-factor theory,”Cognition and Emotion 13 (1999): 181–99CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Midgley, Mary, “The Objection to Systematic Humbug,”Philosophy 53 (1978): 147–69CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Miller, R. L., Brickman, P., and Bolen, D., “Attribution Versus Persuasion as a Means for Modifying Behavior,”Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 31 (1975): 430–41CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Moran, Richard, Authority and Estrangement: An Essay on Self-Knowledge (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2001)Google Scholar
Morris, Herbert, “The Decline of Guilt,” in Ethics and Personality: Essays in Moral Psychology, ed. John Deigh (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1992), 117–31Google Scholar
Murdoch, Iris, The Sovereignty of Good (New York: Routledge, 1970)Google Scholar
Nagel, Thomas, The Possibility of Altruism (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1970); reprinted (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1978)Google Scholar
Nagel, Thomas, “Subjective and Objective,” in his Mortal Questions (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1979), 196–213Google Scholar
Nagel, Thomas, “The Limits of Objectivity,” in The Tanner Lectures on Human Values, Vol. I, ed. S. McMurrin (Salt Lake City: University of Utah Press, 1980), 77–139Google Scholar
Nagel, Thomas, “The Objective Self,” in Knowledge and Mind, ed. Carl Ginet and Sydney Shoemaker (New York: Oxford University Press, 1983), 211–32Google Scholar
Nagel, Thomas, The View From Nowhere (New York: Oxford University Press, 1986), Chapter 4Google Scholar
Nagel, Thomas, “Concealment and Exposure,”Philosophy & Public Affairs 27, no. 1 (Winter 1998): 3–30CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nakhnikian, George, “Love in Human Reason,”Midwest Studies in Philosophy 3 (1978): 286–317CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Neu, Jerome, “Odi et Amo: On Hating the Ones We Love,” in Freud and the Passions, ed. John O'Neill (University Park: Pennsylvania State University Press, 1996), 53–72Google Scholar
Nisbett, R. E., and Valins, S., “Perceiving the causes of one's own behavior,” in Attribution: Perceiving the Causes of Behavior, ed. Edward E. Jones, David E. Kanouse, Harold H. Kelley, Richard E. Nisbett, Stuart Valins, and Bernard Weiner (Morristown, NJ: General Learning, 1972)Google Scholar
Nisbett, R. E., and Wilson, T. D., “Telling more than we can know: Verbal reports of mental processes,”Psychological Review 84 (1977), 231–59CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nozick, Robert, Anarchy, State, and Utopia (New York: Basic, 1974)Google Scholar
Nozick, Robert, Philosophical Explanations (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1981)Google Scholar
Nozick, Robert, The Examined Life (New York: Simon & Schuster, 1989)Google Scholar
Nozick, Robert, The Nature of Rationality (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1993)Google Scholar
Nussbaum, Martha C., “‘Finely Aware and Richly Responsible’: Literature and the Moral Imagination,” in Anti-Theory in Ethics and Moral Conservatism, ed. Stanley G. Clarke and Evan Simpson (Albany: SUNY, 1989), 111–34Google Scholar
Nussbaum, Martha C., “Beatrice's ‘Dante’: Loving the Individual?” in Virtue, Love, and Form: Essays in Memory of Gregory Vlastos, ed. Terence Irwin and Martha C. Nussbaum (Edmonton: Academic Printing & Publishing, 1993), 161–78Google Scholar
Nuttin, Joseph, Motivation, Planning, and Action: a Relational Theory of Behavior Dynamics, transl. Raymond P. Lorion and Jean E. Dumas (Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum, 1984)Google Scholar
O'Brien, Gerard, and Opie, Jonathan, “The Multiplicity of Consciousness and the Emergence of Self,” in The Self in Neuroscience and Psychiatry, ed. Tilo Kirchner and Anthony David (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2003) 107–120Google Scholar
O'Brien, Lucy F., “Anscombe and the Self-Reference Rule,”Analysis 54 (1994): 277–81CrossRefGoogle Scholar
O'Neill, Onora, Acting on Principle: an Essay on Kantian Ethics (New York: Columbia University Press, 1975)Google Scholar
O'Neill, Onora, “Consistency in Action,” in her Constructions of Reason: Explorations of Kant's Practical Philosophy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1989a), 81–104Google Scholar
O'Neill, Onora, “Universal Laws and Ends-in-Themselves,” in her Constructions of Reason: Explorations of Kant's Practical Philosophy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1989b), 126–44Google Scholar
Oldenquist, Andrew, “Loyalties,”Journal of Philosophy 79 (1982): 173–93CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Olson, J. M., “Self-inference processes in emotion,” in Self-Inference Processes: The Ontario Symposium, Vol. 6, ed. James M. Olson and Mark P. Zanna (Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum, 1990), 17–41Google Scholar
Parfit, Derek, Reasons and Persons (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1984)Google Scholar
Paton, H. J., “Kant on Friendship,”Proceedings of the British Academy 42 (1956): 45–66Google Scholar
Peacocke, Christopher, Sense and Content: Experience, Thought, and their Relations (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1983)Google Scholar
Perry, John, A Dialogue on Personal Identity and Immortality (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1978); reprinted in The Problem of the Essential Indexical and Other Essays (New York: Oxford University Press, 1993)Google Scholar
Perry, John “Problem of the Essential Indexical,” Noûs 13 (1979): 3–21; reprinted in his The Problem of the Essential Indexical and Other Essays (New York: Oxford University Press, 1993)Google Scholar
Perry, John, “Self-Notions,” 11 Logos: Philosophic Issues in Christian Perspective (1990): 17–31; reprinted in his The Problem of the Essential Indexical and Other Essays (New York: Oxford University Press, 1993)Google Scholar
Perry, John, The Problem of the Essential Indexical and Other Essays (New York: Oxford University Press, 1993)Google Scholar
Perry, John, “Myself and ‘I’,” in Philosophie in Synthetischer Absicht (A festschrift for Dieter Heinrich), ed. Marcelo Stamm (Stuttgart: Klett-Cotta, 1998), 83–103Google Scholar
Piper, Adrian M. S., “Moral Theory and Moral Alienation,”Journal of Philosophy 84 (1987): 102–18CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Prislin, R., and Pool, G. J., “Behavior, consequences, and the self: Is all well that ends well?”Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin 22 (1996): 933–48CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Railton, Peter, “Alienation, Consequentialism, and the Demands of Morality,”Philosophy and Public Affairs 13 (1984): 134–72Google Scholar
Rawls, John, A Theory of Justice (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1971)Google Scholar
Richardson, Henry S., Practical Reasoning about Final Ends (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1994)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rogers, C. R., Client-Centered Therapy: It's Current Practice, Implications, and Theory (New York: Houghton Mifflin, 1951)Google Scholar
Rorty, Amélie Oksenberg, “The Historicity of Psychological Attitudes: Love Is Not Love which Alters Not when It Alteration Finds,”Midwest Studies in Philosophy 10 (1986): 399–412CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rorty, Richard, “Freud, Morality, and Hermeneutics,”New Literary History 12 (1980): 177–85CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rovane, Carol, “Branching Self-Consciousness”The Philosophical Review 99 (1990): 355–95CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rubin, Jeffrey, “Does the True Self Really Exist? A Critique of Winnicott's True Self Concept,” in his A Psychoanalysis for Our Time: Exploring the Blindness of the Seeing I (New York: New York University Press, 1998)Google Scholar
Ruddick, Sara, “Maternal Thinking,” in Women and Values: Readings in Recent Feminist Philosophy, ed. Marilyn Pearsall (Belmont, CA: Wadsworth, 1986), 340–51Google Scholar
Sandler, Joseph, “On the Concept of the Superego,”The Psychoanalytic Study of the Child 15 (1960): 128–62CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sandler, Joseph, Holder, Alex, and Meers, Dale, “The Ego Ideal and the Ideal Self,”The Psychoanalytic Study of the Child 18 (1963): 139–58CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sartre, Jean-Paul, Being and Nothingness: An Essay on Phenomenological Ontology, transl. Hazel E. Barnes (New York: Philosophical Library, 1956)Google Scholar
Schachter, S., “The interaction of cognitive and physiological determinants of emotional state,” Advances in Experimental Social Psychology, Vol. 1, ed. Leonard Berkowitz (New York: Academic Press, 1964)Google Scholar
Schachter, S., & Singer, J. E., “Cognitive, social and physiological determinants of emotional state,”Psychological Review 69 (1962): 379–99CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schafer, Roy, Aspects of Internalization (New York: International Universities Press, 1968)Google Scholar
Schapiro, Tamar, “What is a Child,”Ethics 109 (1999): 715–38CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Scheffler, Samuel, “Naturalism, Psychoanalysis, and Moral Motivation,” in Psychoanalysis, Mind and Art: Perspectives on Richard Wollheim, ed. Jim Hopkins and Anthony Savile (Oxford: Blackwell, 1992a), 86–109Google Scholar
Scheffler, Samuel, “Reason, Psychology and the Authority of Morality,” Human Morality (New York: Oxford University Press, 1992b), Chapter 5Google Scholar
Scheler, Max, “Über Scham und Schamgefühle,” in Schriften aus dem Nachlass (Bern: Francke Verlag, 1957)Google Scholar
Schreiber, FloraRheta, Sybil (Chicago: Regnery, 1973)
Scruton, Roger, Sexual Desire: A Moral Philosophy of the Erotic (New York: Free Press, 1986)Google Scholar
Setterlund, M. B., and Niedenthal, P. M., “‘Who am I? Why am I here?’: Self-esteem, self-clarity, and prototype matching,”Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 65 (1993): 769–80CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shah, Nishi, “How Truth Governs Belief,”The Philosophical Review 112(2003): 447–82CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shapiro, David, Autonomy and Rigid Character (New York: Basic Books, 1981)Google Scholar
Sherman, S. J., “On the self-erasing nature of errors of prediction,”Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 39 (1980): 211–21CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shoemaker, Sydney, “Persons and Their Pasts,”American Philosophical Quarterly 7 (1970): 269–85Google Scholar
Shoemaker, Sydney, “Embodiment and Behavior,” in The Identities of Persons, ed. Amélie Rorty (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1976), 109–37Google Scholar
Sidgwick, Henry, The Methods of Ethics (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1981)Google Scholar
Simmel, Georg, “The Secret and the Secret Society,” Part IV of The Sociology of Georg Simmel, transl. Kurt H. Wolff (Glencoe, IL: Free Press, 1950)Google Scholar
Slote, Michael, Goods and Virtues (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1983)Google Scholar
Smith, Michael, “The Possibility of Philosophy of Action,” in Human Action, Deliberation and Causation, ed. Jan Bransen and Stefaan Cuypers (Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers, 1998), 17–41Google Scholar
Snyder, M., and Ebbesen, E. B., “Dissonance awareness: A test of dissonance theory versus self-perception theory,”Journal of Experimental Social Psychology 8 (1972): 502–17CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Snygg, D., and Combs, A. W., Individual Behavior: A Perceptual Approach to Behavior (New York: Harper & Brothers, 1959)Google Scholar
Soble, Alan, The Structure of Love (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1990)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Soble, Alan, “Union, Autonomy, and Concern,” in Love Analyzed, ed. Roger E. Lamb (Boulder, CO: Westview, 1997)Google Scholar
Solomon, Robert C., “The Virtue of (Erotic) Love,”Midwest Studies in Philosophy 13 (1988): 12–31CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sommers, Christina Hoff, “Filial Morality,”Journal of Philosophy 83 (1986): 439–56CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Spelman, Elizabeth, “On Treating Persons as Persons,”Ethics 88 (1977): 150–161CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stark, Cynthia A., “Decision Procedures, Standards of Rightness, and Impartiality,”Noûs 31 (1997): 478–95CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Steele, C. M., & Liu, T. J., “Dissonance processes as self-affirmation,”Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 45 (1983): 5–19CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stocker, Michael, “The Schizophrenia of Modern Ethical Theories,”Journal of Philosophy 73 (1976): 453–66CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stocker, Michael, “Values and Purposes: The Limits of Teleology and the Ends of Friendship,”Journal of Philosophy 78 (1981): 747–65Google Scholar
Stocker, Michael, “Friendship and Duty: Some Difficult Relations,” in Identity, Character, and Morality: Essays in Moral Psychology, ed. Owen Flanagan and Amélie Oksenberg Rorty (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1990), 219–33Google Scholar
Stocker, Michael, and Hegeman, Elizabeth, Valuing Emotions (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996)Google Scholar
Stone, J., Cooper, J., Wiegand, A. W., and Aronson, E., “When exemplification fails: Hypocrisy and the motive for self-integrity,”Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 72 (1997): 54–65CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Strawson, P. F., Subject and Predicate in Logic and Grammar (London: Methuen, 1974)Google Scholar
Strawson, P. F., “Kant's Paralogisms: Self-Consciousness and the ‘Outside Observer’,” in Theorie der Subjectivität, ed. Konrad Cramer et al. (Frankfurt: Suhrkamp, 1987), 203–19Google Scholar
Sullivan, Roger J., Kant's Moral Theory (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1989)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Swann, W. B. Jr., “Self-Verification: Bringing Social Reality into Harmony with the Self,” in Psychological Perspectives on the Self, Vol. 2, ed. J. Suls and A. G. Greenwald (Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum, 1983), 33–66Google Scholar
Swann, W. B. Jr., “The Self as Architect of Social Reality,” in The Self and Social Life, ed. Barry R. Schlenker (New York: McGraw-Hill, 1985), 100–25Google Scholar
Swann, W. B. Jr., “To be adored or to be known? The interplay of self-enhancement and self-verification,” in Handbook of Motivation and Cognition: Foundations of Social Behavior, Vol. 2, ed. E. T. Higgins and R. M. Sorrentino (New York: Guilford Press, 1986), 408–48Google Scholar
Swann, W. B. Jr., Self-Traps: The Elusive Quest for Higher Self-Esteem (New York: W. H. Freeman, 1996)Google Scholar
Swann, W. B. Jr., and Brown, J. D., “From Self to health: Self-verification and identity disruption,” in Social Support: An Interactional View, ed. Barbara R. Sarason, Irwin G. Sarason, and Gregory R. Pierce (New York: Wiley-Interscience, 1990), 150–72Google Scholar
Swann, W. B. Jr., Ronde, C., and Hixon, G., “Embracing the bitter ‘truth’: Negative self-concepts and marital commitment,”Psychological Science 3 (1992), 383–86CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Swann, W. B. Jr., Ronde, C., and Hixon, G., “Authenticity and positivity strivings in marriage and courtship,”Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 66 (1994): 857–69CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Swann, W. B. Jr., and Ely, R. J., “A Battle of Wills: Self-Verification Versus Behavioral Confirmation,”Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 46 (1984): 1287–1302CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Swann, W. B. Jr., and Hill, C. A., “When our identities are mistaken: Reaffirming self-conceptions through social interaction,”Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 43 (1982): 59–66CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Swann, W. B. Jr., Hixon, G., Stein-Seroussi, A., and Gilbert, D. T., “The fleeting gleam of praise: Cognitive processes underlying behavioral reactions to self-relevant feedback,”Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 59 (1990): 17–26CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Swann, W. B. Jr., Pelham, B. W., and Krull, D. S., “Agreeable fancy or disagreeable truth? Reconciling self-enhancement and self-verification,”Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 57 (1989): 782–91CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Swann, W. B. Jr., and Predmore, S. C., “Intimates as agents of social support: Sources of consolation or despair?”Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 49 (1985): 1609–17CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Swann, W. B. Jr., and Read, S. J., “Acquiring Self-Knowledge: The Search for Feedback that Fits,”Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 41 (1981a): 1119–1128CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Swann, W. B. Jr., and Read, S. J., “Self-Verification Processes: How We Sustain Our Self-Conceptions,”Journal of Experimental Social Psychology 17 (1981b): 351–72CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Swann, W. B. Jr., Stein-Seroussi, A., and Giesler, R. B., “Why people self-verify,”Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 62 (1992): 392–401CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Taylor, Charles, Human Agency and Language (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1985)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Taylor, Charles, Sources of the Self: The Making of the Modern Identity (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1989)Google Scholar
Taylor, Gabrielle, “Love,”Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 76 (1976): 147–64CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Taylor, Gabrielle, Pride, Shame, and Guilt: Emotions of Self-Assessment (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1985)Google Scholar
Thibodeau, R., and Aronson, E., “Taking a Closer Look: Reasserting the Role of the Self-Concept in Dissonance Theory,”Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin 18 (1992): 91–602CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Thigpen, Corbett H., and Cleckley, Hervey M., The Three Faces of Eve (New York: McGraw-Hill, 1957)Google Scholar
Thomas, Laurence, “Reasons for Loving,” in The Philosophy of (Erotic) Love, ed. Robert C. Solomon and Kathleen M. Higgins (Lawrence: University of Kansas Press, 1991), 467–76Google Scholar
Toner, I. J., Moore, L. P., and Emmons, B. A., “The effects of being labeled on subsequent self-control in children,”Child Development 51 (1980): 618–21CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Torek, Paul, Something to Look Forward To: Personal Identity, Prudence, and Ethics (Ph.D. diss., University of Michigan, 1995)Google Scholar
Trzebinski, J., “Narrative Self, Understanding, and Action,” in The Self in European and North American Culture: Development and Processes, ed. A. Oosterwegel and R. A. Wicklund (Dordrecht: Kluwer, 1995), 73–88Google Scholar
Vallacher, R. R., and Wegner, D. M., A Theory of Action Identification (Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum, 1985)Google Scholar
Vallacher, R. R., and Wegner, D. M., “What Do People Think They're Doing? Action Identification and Human Behavior,”Psychological Review 94 (1987): 3–15CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Velleman, J. David, “Epistemic Freedom,”Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 70 (1989a): 73–97Google Scholar
Velleman, J. David, Practical Reflection (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1989b)Google Scholar
Velleman, J. David, “The Guise of the Good” Noûs 26 (1992a): 3–26; reprinted in his The Possibility of Practical Reason (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2000), Chapter 5Google Scholar
Velleman, J. David, “What Happens When Someone Acts?” Mind 101 (1992b): 461–81; reprinted in his The Possibility of Practical Reason (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2000), Chapter 6Google Scholar
Velleman, J. David, “The Story of Rational Action,” Philosophical Topics 21 (1993): 229–53 (1993); reprinted in his The Possibility of Practical Reason (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2000), Chapter 7Google Scholar
Velleman, J. David, “The Possibility of Practical Reason,” Ethics 106 (1996): 694–726; reprinted in his The Possibility of Practical Reason (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2000), Chapter 8Google Scholar
Velleman, J. David “Deciding How to Decide,” in Ethics and Practical Reason, ed. Garrett Cullity and Berys Gaut (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1997), 29–52; reprinted in his The Possibility of Practical Reason (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2000), Chapter 10Google Scholar
Velleman, J. David, “A Right of Self-Termination?”Ethics 109 (1999): 606–28CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Velleman, J. David, “How to Share an Intention,” in his The Possibility of Practical Reason (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2000a), Chapter 9Google Scholar
Velleman, J. David, “On the Aim of Belief,” in his The Possibility of Practical Reason (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2000b), Chapter 11Google Scholar
Velleman, J. David, The Possibility of Practical Reason (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2000c)Google Scholar
Velleman, J. David, “Narrative Explanation,”The Philosophical Review 112 (2003): 1–25CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Velleman, J. David, “Precis” and “Replies to Discussion” on The Possibility of Practical Reason, Philosophical Studies 121(2004): 225–38, 277–98Google Scholar
Vendler, Zeno, The Matter of Minds (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1984)Google Scholar
Vlastos, Gregory, “Justice and Equality,” in Social Justice, ed. Richard B. Brandt (Englewood Cliffs, N. J.: Prentice Hall, 1962), 31–72Google Scholar
Vlastos, Gregory, “The Individual as an Object of Love in Plato,” in his Platonic Studies (Princeton, N. J.: Princeton University Press, 1973), 3–42Google Scholar
Walton, Kendall L., Mimesis as Make-Believe: On the Foundations of the Representational Arts (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1993)Google Scholar
Wegner, D. M., and , Bargh J. A., “Control and Automaticity in Social Life,” in The Handbook of Social Psychology, 4th ed., Vol. 1, ed. Daniel T. Gilbert, Susan T. Fiske, and Gardner Lindzey (Boston: McGraw-Hill, 1998), 446–96Google Scholar
Wegner, D. M., and Vallacher, R. R., “Action Identification,” in Handbook of Motivation and Cognition, ed. Richard M. Sorrentino and E. Tory Higgins (New York: Guilford Press, 1986), 550–82Google Scholar
Wegner, D. M., Vallacher, R. R., Kiersted, G. W., and Dizadji, D., “Action Identification in the Emergence of Social Behavior,”Social Cognition 4 (1986): 18–38CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Weil, Simone, “Human Personality,” in The Simone Weil Reader, ed. George A. Panichas (New York: David McKay, 1977), 313–39Google Scholar
Westen, Drew, “The Superego: A Revised Developmental Model,”Journal of the American Academy of Psychoanalysis 14 (1986): 181–202CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Whiting, Jennifer, “Impersonal Friends,”Monist 74 (1991): 3–29CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wiggins, David, Identity and Spatio-Temporal Continuity (Oxford: Basic Blackwell, 1967)Google Scholar
Williams, Bernard, “A Critique of Utilitarianism,” in Utilitarianism: For and Against, J. J. C. Smart and Bernard Williams (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1973a), 75–150Google Scholar
Williams, Bernard, “Morality and the Emotions,” in his Problems of the Self (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1973b), 207–29CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Williams, Bernard, “The Imagination and the Self,” in his Problems of the Self (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1973c), 26–45CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Williams, Bernard, “The Self and the Future,” in his Problems of the Self(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1973d), 46–63
Williams, Bernard, “Internal and External Reasons,” in his Moral Luck: Philosophical Papers 19731980 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1981a), 101–13Google Scholar
Williams, Bernard, “Persons, Character and Morality,” in his Moral Luck: Philosophical Papers 1973–1980 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1981b), 1–19CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Williams, Bernard, Shame and Necessity (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1993)Google Scholar
Williams, Bernard, “Internal Reasons and the Obscurity of Blame,” in his Making Sense of Humanity and Other Philosophical Essays (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1995), 39–45CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wilson, Stephen, Feuding, Conflict, and Banditry in Nineteenth-Century Corsica (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1988)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Winnicott, D. W., “Ego Distortion in Terms of True and False Self,” in Collected Papers: Through Paediatrics to Psycho-analysis (London: Tavistock Publications, 1958)Google Scholar
Winnicott, D. W., “Hate in the Countertransference,” Through Paediatrics to Psycho-analysis (London: Hogarth Press, 1975), 194–203Google Scholar
Winnicott, D. W., “Mirror-Role of Mother and Family in Child Development,” in his Playing and Reality (New York: Routledge, 1989), 111–18Google Scholar
Wittgenstein, Ludwig, The Blue and Brown Books (Oxford: Blackwell, 1972)Google Scholar
Wolf, Susan, “Moral Saints,”Journal of Philosophy 79 (1982): 419–39CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wolf, Susan, “Morality and Partiality,”Philosophical Perspectives 6 (1992): 243–59CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wolff, Robert Paul, “There's Nobody Here but Us Persons,” in Women and Philosophy: Toward a Theory of Liberation, ed. Carol C. Gould and Marx W. Wartofsky (New York: G. P. Putnam's Sons, 1976), 128–144Google Scholar
Wollheim, Richard, “Imagination and Identification,” in his On Art and the Mind (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1974), 54–83Google Scholar
Wollheim, Richard, The Thread of Life (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1984)Google Scholar
Wollheim, Richard, Painting as an Art (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1987)Google Scholar
Wollheim, Richard, On the Emotions (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1999)Google Scholar
Yeats, W. B., “For Anne Gregory,” in The Collected Poems of W. B. Yeats (New York: Macmillan, 1956), p. 240Google Scholar
Zanna, M. P., and Cooper, J., “Dissonance and the pill: An attribution approach to studying the arousal properties of dissonance,”Journal of Personality & Social Psychology 29 (1974): 703–709CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Zanna, M. P., Higgins, E. T., and Taves, P. A., “Is dissonance phenomenologically aversive?”Journal of Experimental Social Psychology 12 (1976): 530–538CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Zillman, D., “Attribution and misattribution of excitatory reactions,” New Directions in Attribution Research, Vol. 2, ed. John H. Harvey, William Ickes, and Robert F. Kidd (Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum, 1978), 335–68Google Scholar
Zillman, E., Johnson, R. C., and Day, K. D., “Attribution of apparent arousal and proficiency of recovery for sympathetic activation affecting excitation transfer to aggressive behavior,”Journal of Experimental Social Psychology 10 (1974): 503–15CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Allison, Henry E., Kant's Theory of Freedom (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1990)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Anderson, Elizabeth, Value in Ethics and Economics (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1993)Google Scholar
Andrews, John D. W., The Active Self in Psychotherapy: An Integration of Therapeutic Styles (Boston: Allyn & Bacon, 1991)Google Scholar
Annas, Julia, “Personal Love and Kantian Ethics in Effi Briest,” in Friendship: A Philosophical Reader, ed. Neera Kapur Badhwar (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1993), 155–73Google Scholar
Anscombe, Elizabeth, “The First Person,” in her Metaphysics and the Philosophy of Mind: Collected Papers (Oxford: Blackwell, 1981), 21–36Google Scholar
Anscombe, Elizabeth, Intention (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1957); reprinted (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2000)Google Scholar
Anscombe, Roderick, “The Myth of the True Self,”Psychiatry 52 (1989): 209–17CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Aristotle, Nichomachean Ethics.
Aronson, E., “Dissonance theory: Progress and problems,” in Theories of Cognitive Consistency: A Sourcebook, ed. Robert P. Ableson, Elliot Aronson, William J. McGuire, Theodore M. Newcomb, Milton J. Rosenberg, and Percy H. Tannenbaum (Chicago: Rand McNally, 1968), 5–27Google Scholar
Aronson, E., “The Theory of Cognitive Dissonance: a Current Perspective, Advances in Experimental Social Psychology 4 (1969): 1–34CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Aronson, E., “The Return of the Repressed: Dissonance Theory Makes a Comeback,”Psychological Inquiry 3 (1992): 303–311CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Aronson, E., and Carlsmith, J. M., “Performance expectancy as a determinant of actual performance,”Journal of Abnormal and Social Psychology 65 (1962): 178–82CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Arpaly, Nomy, and Schroeder, Timothy, “Alienation and Externality,”Canadian Journal of Philosophy 29 (1999): 371–387Google Scholar
Augustine, St., The City of God, transl. Marcus Dods (New York: The Modern Library, 1950)Google Scholar
Aune, Bruce, “Speaking of Selves,”Philosophical Quarterly 44 (1994): 279–93CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Badhwar, Neera Kapur, “Friends as Ends in Themselves,”Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 48 (1987): 1–25CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Badhwar, Neera Kapur (listed as Kapur, Neera Badhwar), “Why It Is Wrong to Be Always Guided by the Best: Consequentialism and Friendship,”Ethics 101 (1991): 483–504Google Scholar
Baier, Annette, “The Moral Perils of Intimacy,” in Pragmatism's Freud: The Moral Disposition of Psychoanalysis, ed. Joseph H. Smith and William Kerrigan (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1986), 93–101Google Scholar
Baron, Marcia, “On Admirable Immorality,”Ethics 96 (1986): 557–66CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Baron, Marcia, “Impartiality and Friendship,”Ethics 101 (1991): 836–57CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Baron, Marcia, Kantian Ethics Almost without Apology (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1995)Google Scholar
Baumann, Paul, and Betzler, Monika (eds.), Practical Conflicts: New Philosophical Essays (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2004)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bem, D. J., “Self-perception theory,” in Advances in Experimental Social Psychology, Vol. 6, ed. Leonard Berkowitz (New York: Academic Press, 1972), 1–62Google Scholar
Benhabib, Seyla, “The Generalized and the Concrete Other: The Kohlberg-Gilligan Controversy and Moral Theory,” in Women and Moral Theory, ed. Eva Feder Kittay and Diana T. Meyers (Totowa, NJ: Rowman and Littlefield, 1987), 154–177Google Scholar
Berkowitz, L., “Mood, self-awareness, and willingness to help,”Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 52 (1987): 721–29CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Berkowitz, L., & Turner, C., “Perceived anger level, instigating agent, and aggression,” in Cognitive Alteration of Feeling States, ed. H. London and R. E. Nisbett (Chicago: Aldine, 1974), 174–89Google Scholar
Bermúdez, José Luis, The Paradox of Self-Consciousness (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1998)Google Scholar
Bettelheim, Bruno, Freud and Man's Soul (New York: Vintage, 1984)Google Scholar
Blackburn, Simon, “Has Kant Refuted Parfit?” in Reading Parfit, ed. Jonathan Dancy (Oxford: Blackwell, 1997) 180–202Google Scholar
Blackburn, Simon, Ruling Passions (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1998)Google Scholar
Blum, Lawrence A., Friendship, Altruism and Morality (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1980)Google Scholar
Blum, Lawrence, “Iris Murdoch and the Domain of the Moral,”Philosophical Studies 50 (1986): 343–67CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Boër, Stephen E., and Lycan, William G., Knowing Who (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1986)Google Scholar
Borch-Jacobsen, Mikkel, The Freudian Subject, transl. Catherine Porter (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1988)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brakel, Linda, “Phantasy and Wish: A Proper Function Account for Human A-Rational Primary Process Mediated Mentation,”Australasian Journal of Philosophy 80 (2002): 1–16CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Branden, Nathaniel, “Love and Psychological Visibility,” in Friendship: A Philosophical Reader, ed. Neera Kapur Badhwar (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1993), 64–72Google Scholar
Bratman, Michael, Intention, Plans, and Practical Reason (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1987)Google Scholar
Bratman, Michael, “Identification, Decision, and Treating as a Reason,” in his Faces of Intention (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999), 185–206CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bratman, Michael, “Reflection, Planning, and Temporally Extended Agency,”Philosophical Review 109 (2000): 35–61CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brewer, Bill, “Self-Location and Agency,”Mind 101 (1992): 17–34CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brodt, S. E., and Zimbardo, P. G., “Modifying shyness-related social behavior through symptom misattribution,”Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 41 (1981): 437–49CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Buss, Sarah, and Overton, Lee (eds.) Contours of Agency: Essays on Themes from Harry Frankfurt (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 2002)Google Scholar
Calhoun, Cheshire, “An Apology for Moral Shame” (forthcoming in the Journal of Political Philosophy)
Campbell, John, “The Reductionist View of the Self,” in Reduction, Explanation, and Realism, ed. David Charles and Kathleen Lennon, (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1992), 380–419Google Scholar
Campbell, John, “Self-Reference and Self-Knowledge,” in Past, Space, and Self (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1994), Chapter 4Google Scholar
Cantor, J. R., Zillman, D., and Bryant, J., “Enhancement of experienced sexual arousal in response to erotic stimuli through misattribution of unrelated residual excitation,”Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 32 (1975): 69–75CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cavell, Marcia, “Knowing and Valuing: Some Questions of Genealogy,” in Psychoanalysis, Mind and Art: Perspectives on Richard Wollheim, ed. Jim Hopkins and Anthony Saville (Oxford: Blackwell, 1992), 68–86Google Scholar
Cavell, Stanley, “The Avoidance of Love: A Reading of King Lear,” in his Must We Mean What We Say? A Book of Essays (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1976), 267–353Google Scholar
Cohen, G. A., “Reason, Humanity, and the Moral Law,” in The Sources of Normativity, ed. Onora O'Neill (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996) 167–70Google Scholar
Coltart, Nina, “Attention,” in her Slouching towards Bethlehem (New York: Guildford, 1992), 176–93Google Scholar
Conly, Sarah, “The Objectivity of Morals and the Subjectivity of Agents,”American Philosophical Quarterly 22 (1985): 275–86Google Scholar
Conly, Sarah, “Utilitarianism and Integrity,”Monist 66 (1983): 298–311CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cooper, J., Zanna, M. P., and Taves, P. A., “Arousal as a necessary condition for attitude change following induced compliance,”Journal of Personality & Social Psychology 36 (1978): 1101–1106CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Copp, David, “Korsgaard on Normativity, Identity, and the Ground of Obligation,” in Rationality, Realism, Revision: Proceedings of the Third International Congress of the Society for Analytical Philosophy, vol. 23 of Perspektiven der Analytischen Philosophie, ed. Julian Nida-Rümelin (Berlin: de Gruyter, 1999), 572–581Google Scholar
Cottingham, John, “Ethics and Impartiality,”Philosophical Studies 43 (1983): 83–99CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cross, S. E., and Markus, H. R., “The Willful Self,”Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin 16 (1990): 726–42CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Darwall, Stephen L., “Two Kinds of Respect,”Ethics 88 (1977): 36–49CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Darwall, Stephen L., The British Moralists and the Internal ‘Ought’ 1640–1740 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1995), Chapter 9CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Darwall, Stephen L., “Self-Interest and Self-Concern,”Social Philosophy and Policy 14 (1997): 158–78CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Darwall, Stephen L., “Empathy, Sympathy, Care,”Philosophical Studies 89 (1998): 261–82CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Davidson, D., Essays on Actions and Events (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1980)Google Scholar
Deci, E. L., and Ryan, R. M., “A motivational approach to self: Integration in Personality,” Perspectives on Motivation, Nebraska Symposium on Motivation 1990, ed. Richard Dienstbier (Lincoln: University of Nebraska Press, 1991), 237–88Google Scholar
Deigh, John, “Shame and Self-Esteem: A Critique,”Ethics 93 (1983): 225–45CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Deigh, John, “Freud, Naturalism, and Modern Moral Philosophy,” in his The Sources of Moral Agency: Essays in Moral Psychology and Freudian Theory (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996a), Chapter 6CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Deigh, John, “Remarks on Some Difficulties in Freud's Theory of Moral Development,” in his The Sources of Moral Agency: Essays in Moral Psychology and Freudian Theory (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996b), Chapter 4CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Delaney, Neil, “Romantic Love and Loving Commitment: Articulating a Modern Ideal,”American Philosophical Quarterly 33 (1996): 339–56Google Scholar
Dennett, Daniel, “Where Am I?” in his Brainstorms: Philosophical Essays on Mind and Psychology (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1981), 310–23Google Scholar
Dennett, Daniel, “The Origins of Selves,”Cogito 3 (1989): 163–73CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dennett, Daniel, “The Reality of Selves,” in his Consciousness Explained (Boston: Little, Brown and Company, 1991), Chapter 13Google Scholar
Dennett, Daniel, “The Self as a Center of Narrative Gravity,” in Self and Consciousness: Multiple Perspectives, ed. Frank S. Kessel, Pamela M. Cole, and Dale L. Johnson (Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum Associates, 1992) 103–115Google Scholar
Dennett, Daniel, with Humphrey, Nicholas, “Speaking for Our Selves,” in his Brainchildren: Essays on Designing Minds (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1998), 31–58Google Scholar
Dent, N. J. H., “Duty and Inclination,”Mind 83 (1974): 552–70CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dillon, Robin S., “Respect and Care: Toward Moral Integration,”Canadian Journal of Philosophy 22 (1992a): 105–32CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dillon, Robin S., “Toward a Feminist Conception of Self-Respect,”Hypatia 7 (1992b): 52–69CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dipboye, R. L., “A critical review of Korman's self-consistency theory of work motivation and occupational choice,”Organizational Behavior and Human Performance 18 (1977): 108–26CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Downie, R. S., and Telfer, Elizabeth, Respect for Persons (New York: Shocken, 1970)Google Scholar
Seuss, Dr., Horton Hears a Who! (New York: Random House, 1954)Google Scholar
Seuss, Dr., Happy Birthday to You! (New York: Random House, 1959)Google Scholar
Eagle, Morris, “Psychoanalysis and the Personal,” in Mind, Psychoanalysis and Science, ed. P. Clark and C. Wright (Oxford: Blackwell, 1988), 91–111Google Scholar
Eagle, Morris, “Psychoanalytic Conceptions of the Self,” in The Self: Interdisciplinary Approaches, ed. J. Strauss and G. R. Goethals (New York: Springer-Verlag, 1991), 49–65Google Scholar
Eisenberg, N., Cialdini, R. B., McCreath, H., and Shell, R., “Consistency-based compliance: When and why do children become vulnerable?”Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 52 (1987): 1174–81CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Eisenberg, N., Cialdini, R. B., McCreath, H., and Shell, R., “Consistency-based compliance in children: When and why do consistency procedures have immediate effects?”International Journal of Behavioural Development 12 (1989): 351–67CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Eliot, George, Felix Holt (London: Penguin, 1995)Google Scholar
Elliot, A. J., and Devine, P. G., “On the motivational nature of cognitive dissonance: Dissonance as psychological discomfort,”Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 67 (1994): 382–94CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ellison, Ralph, Invisible Man (New York: New American Library, 1952)Google Scholar
Elster, Jon, Strong Feelings: Emotion, Addiction, and Human Behavior (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1999)Google Scholar
Epstein, Mark, Thoughts Without a Thinker: Psychotherapy From a Buddhist Perspective (New York: Basic Books, 1995)Google Scholar
Epstein, S., “The Self-Concept Revisited; Or a Theory of a Theory,”American Psychologist 28 (1973): 404–416CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Epstein, S., “The Unity Principle Versus the Reality and Pleasure Principles, Or the Tale of the Scorpion and the Frog,” in Self-Concept: Advances in Theory and Research, ed. M. D. Lynch, A. A. Norem-Hebeisen, and K. J. Gergen (Cambridge, MA: Ballinger, 1981)Google Scholar
Erikson, Erik, Identity, Youth, and Crisis (New York: W. W. Norton, 1968), 74–90Google Scholar
Evans, Gareth, The Varieties of Reference (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1982)Google Scholar
Fairbairn, W. R. D., Psychoanalytic Studies of the Personality (London: Routledge, 1990)Google Scholar
Fazio, R. H., Zanna, M. P., and Cooper, J., “Dissonance and self-perception: An integrative view of each theory's proper domain of application,”Journal of Experimental Social Psychology 13 (1977): 464–479CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Festinger, L., and Carlsmith, J. M., “Cognitive Consequences of Forced Compliance,”Journal of Abnormal and Social Psychology 58 (1959), 203–11CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Flanagan, Owen, “Multiple Identity, Character Transformation, and Self-Reclamation,” in Philosophical Psychopathology, eds. G. Graham and Lynn Stephens, (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1994), Chapter 7; reprinted in his Self Expressions (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1996), 65–87Google Scholar
Foot, Philippa, “Are Moral Considerations Overriding?” in her Virtues and Vices (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1978a), 181–88Google Scholar
Foot, Philippa, “Morality as a System of Hypothetical Imperatives,” in her Virtues and Vices (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1978b), 157–73Google Scholar
Frankena, William K., “The Ethics of Respect for Persons,”Philosophical Topics 14 (1986): 149–67CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Frankfurt, Harry, “Identification and Wholeheartedness,” in his The Importance of What We Care About (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1988a), Chapter 12CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Frankfurt, Harry, “Rationality and the Unthinkable,” in his The Importance of What We Care About (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1988b), Chapter 13CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Frankfurt, Harry, The Importance of What We Care About (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1988c)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Frankfurt, Harry, “Autonomy, Necessity, and Love,” in Vernunftbegriffe in der Moderne, ed. Hans Friedrich Fulda and Rolf-Peter Horstmann (Klett-Cotta, 1994), 433–47; reprinted in his Necessity, Volition, and Love (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1999)Google Scholar
Frankfurt, Harry, “Some Thoughts about Caring,”Ethical Perspectives 5 (1998): 3–14CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Frankfurt, Harry, “On the Necessity of Ideals,” in his Necessity, Volition, and Love (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999a), Chapter 9Google Scholar
Frankfurt, Harry, “The Faintest Passion,” in his Necessity, Volition, and Love (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999b), Chapter 8Google Scholar
Frankfurt, Harry, Necessity, Volition, and Love (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999c)Google Scholar
Freedman, J. L., and Fraser, S. C., “Compliance without pressure: The foot-in-the-door technique,” Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 4 (1966): 195–202Google Scholar
Freud, Anna, The Ego and the Mechanisms of Defense (London: Hogarth Press, 1937), 109–121; reprinted in Pivotal Papers on Identification, ed. George H. Pollock (Madison, CT: International Universities Press, 1993), 105–14Google Scholar
Freud, Sigmund, “Group Psychology and the Analysis of the Ego,” in S. E., vol. 18, 67–143
Freud, Sigmund, “Instincts and Their Vicissitudes,” in S. E., vol. 14, 111–40
Freud, Sigmund, “Notes Upon a Case of Obsessional Neurosis,” in S. E., vol. 10, 153–249
Freud, Sigmund, “Observations on Transference-Love,” in S. E., vol. 12, 157–71
Freud, Sigmund, “On Narcissism: An Introduction,” in S. E., vol. 14, 67–102
Freud, Sigmund, “Psycho-Analysis,” in S. E., vol. 20, 261–70
Freud, Sigmund, “Recommendations to Physicians Practicing Psycho-Analysis,” in S. E., vol. 12, 111–20
Freud, Sigmund, “The Economic Problem of Masochism,” in S. E., vol. 19, 156–70
Freud, Sigmund, “The Libido Theory,” in S. E., vol. 18, 255–59
Freud, Sigmund, “Three Essays on the Theory of Sexuality,” in S. E., vol. 7, 125–243
Freud, Sigmund, An Autobiographical Study, in S. E., vol. 20, 3–74
Freud, Sigmund, Civilization and Its Discontents, S. E., vol. 21, 59–145
Freud, Sigmund, Five Lectures on Psychoanalysis, in S. E., vol. 11, 3–55
Freud, Sigmund, Group Psychology, in S. E., vol. 18, 69–143
Freud, Sigmund, Inhibitions, Symptoms and Anxiety, in S. E., vol. 20, 77–175
Freud, Sigmund, Introductory Lectures on Psychoanalysis, in S. E., vol. 16
Freud, Sigmund, Moses and Monotheism, in S. E., vol. 23, 3–137
Freud, Sigmund, New Introductory Lectures in Psychoanalysis, in S. E., vol. 22, 3–182
Freud, Sigmund, Outline of Psychoanalysis, in S. E., vol. 23, 141–207
Freud, Sigmund, The Ego and the Id, in S. E., vol. 19, 3–66CrossRef
Freud, Sigmund, The Standard Edition of the Complete Psychological Works of Sigmund Freud, ed. James Strachey et al. (London: Hogarth Press and the Institute of Psycho-Analysis, 1953–1974)Google Scholar
Freud, Sigmund, Totem and Taboo, in S. E., vol. 13, ix–162
Gewirth, Alan, “Ethical Universalism and Particularism,”Journal of Philosophy 85 (1988): 283–302CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gibbard, Allan, Wise Choices, Apt Feelings: A Theory of Normative Judgment (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1990)Google Scholar
Gilbert, Margaret, On Social Facts (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1992)Google Scholar
Goldman, M., Seever, M., and Seever, M., “Social labeling and the foot-in-the-door effect,”The Journal of Social Psychology 117 (1982): 19–23CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gorasini, D. R., and Olson, J. M., “Does self-perception change explain the foot-in-the-door effect?”Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 69 (1995): 91–105CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Green, O. H., The Emotions: A Philosophical Theory (Boston: Kluwer, 1992)Google Scholar
Green, O. H., “Is Love an Emotion?” Love Analyzed, ed. Roger E. Lamb (Boulder, CO.: Westview, 1997) 209–24Google Scholar
Greenspan, Patricia, Emotions and Reason: An Inquiry into Emotional Justification (New York: Routledge, 1988)Google Scholar
Greenwald, A. G., Carnot, C. G., Beach, R., and Young, B., “Increasing Voting Behavior by Asking People if They Expect to Vote,”Journal of Applied Psychology 72 (1987): 315–18CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Grusec, J. E., and Redler, E., “Attribution, reinforcement, and altruism: A developmental analysis,”Developmental Psychology 16 (1980): 525–34CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Guyer, Paul, “The Possibility of the Categorical Imperative,”Philosophical Review 104 (1995): 353–85CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hamilton, Andy, “A New Look at Personal Identity,”The Philosophical Quarterly 45 (1995): 332–49CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hardcastle, Valerie Gray, and Flanagan, Owen, “Multiplex vs. Multiple Selves: Distinguishing Dissociative Disorders,”The Monist 82 (1999): 645–57CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Harman, Gilbert, Change in View: Principles of Reasoning (Cambridge, MA: Bradford Books, 1986)Google Scholar
Harmon-Jones, E., and Mills, J. (eds.), Cognitive Dissonance: Progress on a Pivotal Theory in Social Psychology (Washington, DC: American Psychological Association, 1999)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Harré, Rom, Social Being (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1979)Google Scholar
Harré, Rom, The Singular Self: An Introduction to the Psychology of Personhood (London: Sage Publications, 1998)Google Scholar
Hatzimoysis, Anthony (ed.), Philosophy and the Emotions (New York: Cambridge University Press, 2003)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hawthorne, Nathaniel, The Scarlet Letter (New York: Bantam Books, 1986)Google Scholar
Herman, Barbara, The Practice of Moral Judgement (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1993)Google Scholar
Higgins, E. T., Rhodewalt, F., and Zanna, M. P., “Dissonance motivation: Its nature, persistence, and reinstatement,”Journal of Experimental Social Psychology 15 (1979): 16–34CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hill, Thomas E. Jr., “Humanity as an End in Itself,” in his Dignity and Practical Reason in Kant's Moral Theory (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1992), 38–57Google Scholar
Hollis, Martin, Models of Man (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1977)Google Scholar
Hussain, Nadeem, “The Guise of A Reason,” 121(2004) Philosophical Studies: 263–75CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ishiguro, Hidé, “Imagination II,”Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society Supp. Vol. 41 (1967): 37–56Google Scholar
Jackson, Frank, “Decision-Theoretic Consequentialism and the Nearest and Dearest Objection,”Ethics 101 (1991): 461–82CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jensen, R. E., and Moore, S. G., “The effect of attribute statements on cooperativeness and competitiveness in school-age boys,”Child Development 48 (1977): 305–07CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jeske, Diane, “Friendship, Virtue, and Impartiality,”Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 57 (1997): 51–72CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Johnson, Edward, “Ignoring Persons,” in Respect for Persons, ed. O. H. Green, Tulane Studies in Philosophy 31 (1982): 91–105Google Scholar
Jones, David H., “Freud's Theory of Moral Conscience,”Philosophy 41 (1966): 34–57CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jussim, L., Eccles, J., and Madon, S., “Social perception, social stereotypes, and teacher expectations: Accuracy and the quest for the powerful self-fulfilling prophecy,” in Advances in Experimental Social Psychology, Vol. 28, ed. M. P. Zanna (New York: Academic Press, 1996), 281–388Google Scholar
Jussim, L., Yen, H. J., and Aiello, J. R., “Self-consistency, self-enhancement, and accuracy in reactions to feedback,”Journal of Experimental and Social Psychology 31 (1995): 322–56CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kant, Immanuel, Critique of Practical Reason, transl. Lewis White Beck (Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill, 1956)Google Scholar
Kant, Immanuel, Groundwork of the Metaphysic of Morals, transl. H. J. Paton (New York: Harper and Row, 1964)Google Scholar
Kant, Immanuel, Critique of Pure Reason, transl. Norman Kemp Smith (New York: St. Martin's Press, 1965)Google Scholar
Kant, Immmanuel, “On the Proverb: That May be True in Theory, But Is of No Practical Use,” in Perpetual Peace and Other Essays, transl. Ted Humphrey (Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing, 1983), 61–92Google Scholar
Kant, Immanuel, The Metaphysics of Morals, transl. Mary Gregor (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kant, Immanuel, Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals, transl. Mary Gregor (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1997)Google Scholar
Kavka, Gregory, “The Toxin Puzzle,”Analysis 43 (1983): 33–36CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kekes, John, “Morality and Impartiality,”American Philosophical Quarterly 18 (1981): 295–303Google Scholar
Kelley, H. H., “Attribution theory in social psychology,” in Nebraska Symposium on Motivation, 1967, Vol. 15 of Current Theory and Research in Motivation, ed. David Levine (Lincoln: University of Nebraska Press, 1967), 192–238Google Scholar
Kihlstrom, J. F., and Cantor, N., “Mental Representations of the Self,” in Advances in Experimental and Social Psychology, ed. L. Berkowitz (New York: Academic Press, 1984), vol. 17, 2–40Google Scholar
Korman, A. K., “Toward an Hypothesis of Work Behavior,” 54 Journal of Applied Psychology 54 (1970): 31–41CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Korsgaard, Christine, “Skepticism about Practical Reason,”Journal of Philosophy 83 (1986): 5–25CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Korsgaard, Christine, “An Introduction to the Ethical, Political, and Religious Thought of Kant,” in her Creating the Kingdom of Ends (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996a), 3–42CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Korsgaard, Christine, “Kant's Analysis of Obligation: the Argument of Groundwork I,” in her Creating the Kingdom of Ends (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996b), 43–76CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Korsgaard, Christine, “Kant's Formula of Universal Law,” in her Creating the Kingdom of Ends (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996c), 77–105CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Korsgaard, Christine, (with Cohen, G. A., Raymond Geuss, , Thomas Nagel, , and Bernard Williams, ), The Sources of Normativity, ed. Onora O'Neill. (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996d)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Korsgaard, Christine, “The Normativity of Instrumental Reason, in Ethics and Practical Reason, ed. Garrett Cullity & Berys Gaut (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1997), 213–54Google Scholar
Korsgaard, Christine, “Self-Constitution in the Ethics of Plato and Kant,”Journal of Ethics 3 (1999): 1–29CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kraut, R. E., “Effects of social labeling on giving to charity,”Journal of Experimental Social Psychology (1973): 551–62CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kraut, Robert, “Love De Re,”Midwest Studies in Philosophy 10 (1986): 413–30CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lamb, Roger E., “Love and Rationality,” in Love Analyzed, ed. Roger E. Lamb (Boulder, CO: Westview, 1997), 23–47Google Scholar
Lampl-de Groot, Jeanne, “Ego Ideal and Superego,”The Psychoanalytic Study of the Child 17 (1962): 94–106CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lecky, P., Self-Consistency: A Theory of Personality (New York: Island Press, 1945)Google Scholar
Levine, Frederic J., and Kravis, Robert, “Psychoanalytic Theories of the Self: Contrasting Clinical Approaches to the New Narcissism,” in The Book of the Self: Person, Pretext, and Process, ed. Polly Young-Eisendrath and James A. Hall (New York: New York University Press, 1987), 306–330Google Scholar
Lewis, David, “Attitudes De Dicto and De Se,”The Philosophical Review 88 (1979): 513–14CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Locke, John, An Essay Concerning Human Understanding, ed. Peter H. Nidditch (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1975)Google Scholar
Lyons, William G., Emotion (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1980)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lycan, William G., Consciousness (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1987)Google Scholar
Mackie, John, “The Transcendental ‘I’,” in Philosophical Subjects: Essays Presented to P. F. Strawson, ed. Zak van Straaten (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1980), 48–61Google Scholar
Madell, Geoffrey, “Personal Identity and the Idea of a Human Being,” in Human Beings, ed. David Cockburn (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991), 127–42Google Scholar
Malcolm, Janet, Psychoanalysis: The Impossible Profession (New York: Vintage Press, 1980)Google Scholar
Maracek, J., & Mettee, D. R., “Avoidance of continued success as a function of self-esteem, level of esteem certainty, and responsibility for success,”Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 22 (1972): 98–107CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Martin, Raymond, “Having the Experience: The Next Best Thing to Being There,”Philosophical Studies 70 (1993): 305–21CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mason, Michelle, Moral Virtue and Reasons for Action, (Ph.D. diss.: University of Chicago, 2001)Google Scholar
McFall, Lynne, “Integrity,”Ethics 98 (1987): 5–20CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McNulty, S. E., and Swann, W. B. Jr., “Psychotherapy, Self-Concept Change, and Self-Verification,” in The Relational Self: Theoretical Convergences in Psychoanalysis and Social Psychology, ed. Rebecca C. Curtis (New York: Guildford Press, 1991), 213–37Google Scholar
Mellor, D. H., “I and Now,” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 89 (1989): 79–94; reprinted in his Matters of Metaphysics (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991)Google Scholar
Mezzacappa, E. S., Katkin, E. S., and Palmer, S. N., “Epinephrine, arousal, and emotion: A new look at two-factor theory,”Cognition and Emotion 13 (1999): 181–99CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Midgley, Mary, “The Objection to Systematic Humbug,”Philosophy 53 (1978): 147–69CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Miller, R. L., Brickman, P., and Bolen, D., “Attribution Versus Persuasion as a Means for Modifying Behavior,”Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 31 (1975): 430–41CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Moran, Richard, Authority and Estrangement: An Essay on Self-Knowledge (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2001)Google Scholar
Morris, Herbert, “The Decline of Guilt,” in Ethics and Personality: Essays in Moral Psychology, ed. John Deigh (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1992), 117–31Google Scholar
Murdoch, Iris, The Sovereignty of Good (New York: Routledge, 1970)Google Scholar
Nagel, Thomas, The Possibility of Altruism (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1970); reprinted (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1978)Google Scholar
Nagel, Thomas, “Subjective and Objective,” in his Mortal Questions (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1979), 196–213Google Scholar
Nagel, Thomas, “The Limits of Objectivity,” in The Tanner Lectures on Human Values, Vol. I, ed. S. McMurrin (Salt Lake City: University of Utah Press, 1980), 77–139Google Scholar
Nagel, Thomas, “The Objective Self,” in Knowledge and Mind, ed. Carl Ginet and Sydney Shoemaker (New York: Oxford University Press, 1983), 211–32Google Scholar
Nagel, Thomas, The View From Nowhere (New York: Oxford University Press, 1986), Chapter 4Google Scholar
Nagel, Thomas, “Concealment and Exposure,”Philosophy & Public Affairs 27, no. 1 (Winter 1998): 3–30CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nakhnikian, George, “Love in Human Reason,”Midwest Studies in Philosophy 3 (1978): 286–317CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Neu, Jerome, “Odi et Amo: On Hating the Ones We Love,” in Freud and the Passions, ed. John O'Neill (University Park: Pennsylvania State University Press, 1996), 53–72Google Scholar
Nisbett, R. E., and Valins, S., “Perceiving the causes of one's own behavior,” in Attribution: Perceiving the Causes of Behavior, ed. Edward E. Jones, David E. Kanouse, Harold H. Kelley, Richard E. Nisbett, Stuart Valins, and Bernard Weiner (Morristown, NJ: General Learning, 1972)Google Scholar
Nisbett, R. E., and Wilson, T. D., “Telling more than we can know: Verbal reports of mental processes,”Psychological Review 84 (1977), 231–59CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nozick, Robert, Anarchy, State, and Utopia (New York: Basic, 1974)Google Scholar
Nozick, Robert, Philosophical Explanations (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1981)Google Scholar
Nozick, Robert, The Examined Life (New York: Simon & Schuster, 1989)Google Scholar
Nozick, Robert, The Nature of Rationality (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1993)Google Scholar
Nussbaum, Martha C., “‘Finely Aware and Richly Responsible’: Literature and the Moral Imagination,” in Anti-Theory in Ethics and Moral Conservatism, ed. Stanley G. Clarke and Evan Simpson (Albany: SUNY, 1989), 111–34Google Scholar
Nussbaum, Martha C., “Beatrice's ‘Dante’: Loving the Individual?” in Virtue, Love, and Form: Essays in Memory of Gregory Vlastos, ed. Terence Irwin and Martha C. Nussbaum (Edmonton: Academic Printing & Publishing, 1993), 161–78Google Scholar
Nuttin, Joseph, Motivation, Planning, and Action: a Relational Theory of Behavior Dynamics, transl. Raymond P. Lorion and Jean E. Dumas (Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum, 1984)Google Scholar
O'Brien, Gerard, and Opie, Jonathan, “The Multiplicity of Consciousness and the Emergence of Self,” in The Self in Neuroscience and Psychiatry, ed. Tilo Kirchner and Anthony David (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2003) 107–120Google Scholar
O'Brien, Lucy F., “Anscombe and the Self-Reference Rule,”Analysis 54 (1994): 277–81CrossRefGoogle Scholar
O'Neill, Onora, Acting on Principle: an Essay on Kantian Ethics (New York: Columbia University Press, 1975)Google Scholar
O'Neill, Onora, “Consistency in Action,” in her Constructions of Reason: Explorations of Kant's Practical Philosophy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1989a), 81–104Google Scholar
O'Neill, Onora, “Universal Laws and Ends-in-Themselves,” in her Constructions of Reason: Explorations of Kant's Practical Philosophy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1989b), 126–44Google Scholar
Oldenquist, Andrew, “Loyalties,”Journal of Philosophy 79 (1982): 173–93CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Olson, J. M., “Self-inference processes in emotion,” in Self-Inference Processes: The Ontario Symposium, Vol. 6, ed. James M. Olson and Mark P. Zanna (Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum, 1990), 17–41Google Scholar
Parfit, Derek, Reasons and Persons (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1984)Google Scholar
Paton, H. J., “Kant on Friendship,”Proceedings of the British Academy 42 (1956): 45–66Google Scholar
Peacocke, Christopher, Sense and Content: Experience, Thought, and their Relations (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1983)Google Scholar
Perry, John, A Dialogue on Personal Identity and Immortality (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1978); reprinted in The Problem of the Essential Indexical and Other Essays (New York: Oxford University Press, 1993)Google Scholar
Perry, John “Problem of the Essential Indexical,” Noûs 13 (1979): 3–21; reprinted in his The Problem of the Essential Indexical and Other Essays (New York: Oxford University Press, 1993)Google Scholar
Perry, John, “Self-Notions,” 11 Logos: Philosophic Issues in Christian Perspective (1990): 17–31; reprinted in his The Problem of the Essential Indexical and Other Essays (New York: Oxford University Press, 1993)Google Scholar
Perry, John, The Problem of the Essential Indexical and Other Essays (New York: Oxford University Press, 1993)Google Scholar
Perry, John, “Myself and ‘I’,” in Philosophie in Synthetischer Absicht (A festschrift for Dieter Heinrich), ed. Marcelo Stamm (Stuttgart: Klett-Cotta, 1998), 83–103Google Scholar
Piper, Adrian M. S., “Moral Theory and Moral Alienation,”Journal of Philosophy 84 (1987): 102–18CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Prislin, R., and Pool, G. J., “Behavior, consequences, and the self: Is all well that ends well?”Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin 22 (1996): 933–48CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Railton, Peter, “Alienation, Consequentialism, and the Demands of Morality,”Philosophy and Public Affairs 13 (1984): 134–72Google Scholar
Rawls, John, A Theory of Justice (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1971)Google Scholar
Richardson, Henry S., Practical Reasoning about Final Ends (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1994)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rogers, C. R., Client-Centered Therapy: It's Current Practice, Implications, and Theory (New York: Houghton Mifflin, 1951)Google Scholar
Rorty, Amélie Oksenberg, “The Historicity of Psychological Attitudes: Love Is Not Love which Alters Not when It Alteration Finds,”Midwest Studies in Philosophy 10 (1986): 399–412CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rorty, Richard, “Freud, Morality, and Hermeneutics,”New Literary History 12 (1980): 177–85CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rovane, Carol, “Branching Self-Consciousness”The Philosophical Review 99 (1990): 355–95CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rubin, Jeffrey, “Does the True Self Really Exist? A Critique of Winnicott's True Self Concept,” in his A Psychoanalysis for Our Time: Exploring the Blindness of the Seeing I (New York: New York University Press, 1998)Google Scholar
Ruddick, Sara, “Maternal Thinking,” in Women and Values: Readings in Recent Feminist Philosophy, ed. Marilyn Pearsall (Belmont, CA: Wadsworth, 1986), 340–51Google Scholar
Sandler, Joseph, “On the Concept of the Superego,”The Psychoanalytic Study of the Child 15 (1960): 128–62CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sandler, Joseph, Holder, Alex, and Meers, Dale, “The Ego Ideal and the Ideal Self,”The Psychoanalytic Study of the Child 18 (1963): 139–58CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sartre, Jean-Paul, Being and Nothingness: An Essay on Phenomenological Ontology, transl. Hazel E. Barnes (New York: Philosophical Library, 1956)Google Scholar
Schachter, S., “The interaction of cognitive and physiological determinants of emotional state,” Advances in Experimental Social Psychology, Vol. 1, ed. Leonard Berkowitz (New York: Academic Press, 1964)Google Scholar
Schachter, S., & Singer, J. E., “Cognitive, social and physiological determinants of emotional state,”Psychological Review 69 (1962): 379–99CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schafer, Roy, Aspects of Internalization (New York: International Universities Press, 1968)Google Scholar
Schapiro, Tamar, “What is a Child,”Ethics 109 (1999): 715–38CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Scheffler, Samuel, “Naturalism, Psychoanalysis, and Moral Motivation,” in Psychoanalysis, Mind and Art: Perspectives on Richard Wollheim, ed. Jim Hopkins and Anthony Savile (Oxford: Blackwell, 1992a), 86–109Google Scholar
Scheffler, Samuel, “Reason, Psychology and the Authority of Morality,” Human Morality (New York: Oxford University Press, 1992b), Chapter 5Google Scholar
Scheler, Max, “Über Scham und Schamgefühle,” in Schriften aus dem Nachlass (Bern: Francke Verlag, 1957)Google Scholar
Schreiber, FloraRheta, Sybil (Chicago: Regnery, 1973)
Scruton, Roger, Sexual Desire: A Moral Philosophy of the Erotic (New York: Free Press, 1986)Google Scholar
Setterlund, M. B., and Niedenthal, P. M., “‘Who am I? Why am I here?’: Self-esteem, self-clarity, and prototype matching,”Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 65 (1993): 769–80CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shah, Nishi, “How Truth Governs Belief,”The Philosophical Review 112(2003): 447–82CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shapiro, David, Autonomy and Rigid Character (New York: Basic Books, 1981)Google Scholar
Sherman, S. J., “On the self-erasing nature of errors of prediction,”Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 39 (1980): 211–21CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shoemaker, Sydney, “Persons and Their Pasts,”American Philosophical Quarterly 7 (1970): 269–85Google Scholar
Shoemaker, Sydney, “Embodiment and Behavior,” in The Identities of Persons, ed. Amélie Rorty (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1976), 109–37Google Scholar
Sidgwick, Henry, The Methods of Ethics (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1981)Google Scholar
Simmel, Georg, “The Secret and the Secret Society,” Part IV of The Sociology of Georg Simmel, transl. Kurt H. Wolff (Glencoe, IL: Free Press, 1950)Google Scholar
Slote, Michael, Goods and Virtues (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1983)Google Scholar
Smith, Michael, “The Possibility of Philosophy of Action,” in Human Action, Deliberation and Causation, ed. Jan Bransen and Stefaan Cuypers (Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers, 1998), 17–41Google Scholar
Snyder, M., and Ebbesen, E. B., “Dissonance awareness: A test of dissonance theory versus self-perception theory,”Journal of Experimental Social Psychology 8 (1972): 502–17CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Snygg, D., and Combs, A. W., Individual Behavior: A Perceptual Approach to Behavior (New York: Harper & Brothers, 1959)Google Scholar
Soble, Alan, The Structure of Love (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1990)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Soble, Alan, “Union, Autonomy, and Concern,” in Love Analyzed, ed. Roger E. Lamb (Boulder, CO: Westview, 1997)Google Scholar
Solomon, Robert C., “The Virtue of (Erotic) Love,”Midwest Studies in Philosophy 13 (1988): 12–31CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sommers, Christina Hoff, “Filial Morality,”Journal of Philosophy 83 (1986): 439–56CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Spelman, Elizabeth, “On Treating Persons as Persons,”Ethics 88 (1977): 150–161CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stark, Cynthia A., “Decision Procedures, Standards of Rightness, and Impartiality,”Noûs 31 (1997): 478–95CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Steele, C. M., & Liu, T. J., “Dissonance processes as self-affirmation,”Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 45 (1983): 5–19CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stocker, Michael, “The Schizophrenia of Modern Ethical Theories,”Journal of Philosophy 73 (1976): 453–66CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stocker, Michael, “Values and Purposes: The Limits of Teleology and the Ends of Friendship,”Journal of Philosophy 78 (1981): 747–65Google Scholar
Stocker, Michael, “Friendship and Duty: Some Difficult Relations,” in Identity, Character, and Morality: Essays in Moral Psychology, ed. Owen Flanagan and Amélie Oksenberg Rorty (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1990), 219–33Google Scholar
Stocker, Michael, and Hegeman, Elizabeth, Valuing Emotions (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996)Google Scholar
Stone, J., Cooper, J., Wiegand, A. W., and Aronson, E., “When exemplification fails: Hypocrisy and the motive for self-integrity,”Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 72 (1997): 54–65CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Strawson, P. F., Subject and Predicate in Logic and Grammar (London: Methuen, 1974)Google Scholar
Strawson, P. F., “Kant's Paralogisms: Self-Consciousness and the ‘Outside Observer’,” in Theorie der Subjectivität, ed. Konrad Cramer et al. (Frankfurt: Suhrkamp, 1987), 203–19Google Scholar
Sullivan, Roger J., Kant's Moral Theory (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1989)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Swann, W. B. Jr., “Self-Verification: Bringing Social Reality into Harmony with the Self,” in Psychological Perspectives on the Self, Vol. 2, ed. J. Suls and A. G. Greenwald (Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum, 1983), 33–66Google Scholar
Swann, W. B. Jr., “The Self as Architect of Social Reality,” in The Self and Social Life, ed. Barry R. Schlenker (New York: McGraw-Hill, 1985), 100–25Google Scholar
Swann, W. B. Jr., “To be adored or to be known? The interplay of self-enhancement and self-verification,” in Handbook of Motivation and Cognition: Foundations of Social Behavior, Vol. 2, ed. E. T. Higgins and R. M. Sorrentino (New York: Guilford Press, 1986), 408–48Google Scholar
Swann, W. B. Jr., Self-Traps: The Elusive Quest for Higher Self-Esteem (New York: W. H. Freeman, 1996)Google Scholar
Swann, W. B. Jr., and Brown, J. D., “From Self to health: Self-verification and identity disruption,” in Social Support: An Interactional View, ed. Barbara R. Sarason, Irwin G. Sarason, and Gregory R. Pierce (New York: Wiley-Interscience, 1990), 150–72Google Scholar
Swann, W. B. Jr., Ronde, C., and Hixon, G., “Embracing the bitter ‘truth’: Negative self-concepts and marital commitment,”Psychological Science 3 (1992), 383–86CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Swann, W. B. Jr., Ronde, C., and Hixon, G., “Authenticity and positivity strivings in marriage and courtship,”Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 66 (1994): 857–69CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Swann, W. B. Jr., and Ely, R. J., “A Battle of Wills: Self-Verification Versus Behavioral Confirmation,”Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 46 (1984): 1287–1302CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Swann, W. B. Jr., and Hill, C. A., “When our identities are mistaken: Reaffirming self-conceptions through social interaction,”Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 43 (1982): 59–66CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Swann, W. B. Jr., Hixon, G., Stein-Seroussi, A., and Gilbert, D. T., “The fleeting gleam of praise: Cognitive processes underlying behavioral reactions to self-relevant feedback,”Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 59 (1990): 17–26CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Swann, W. B. Jr., Pelham, B. W., and Krull, D. S., “Agreeable fancy or disagreeable truth? Reconciling self-enhancement and self-verification,”Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 57 (1989): 782–91CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Swann, W. B. Jr., and Predmore, S. C., “Intimates as agents of social support: Sources of consolation or despair?”Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 49 (1985): 1609–17CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Swann, W. B. Jr., and Read, S. J., “Acquiring Self-Knowledge: The Search for Feedback that Fits,”Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 41 (1981a): 1119–1128CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Swann, W. B. Jr., and Read, S. J., “Self-Verification Processes: How We Sustain Our Self-Conceptions,”Journal of Experimental Social Psychology 17 (1981b): 351–72CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Swann, W. B. Jr., Stein-Seroussi, A., and Giesler, R. B., “Why people self-verify,”Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 62 (1992): 392–401CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Taylor, Charles, Human Agency and Language (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1985)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Taylor, Charles, Sources of the Self: The Making of the Modern Identity (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1989)Google Scholar
Taylor, Gabrielle, “Love,”Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 76 (1976): 147–64CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Taylor, Gabrielle, Pride, Shame, and Guilt: Emotions of Self-Assessment (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1985)Google Scholar
Thibodeau, R., and Aronson, E., “Taking a Closer Look: Reasserting the Role of the Self-Concept in Dissonance Theory,”Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin 18 (1992): 91–602CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Thigpen, Corbett H., and Cleckley, Hervey M., The Three Faces of Eve (New York: McGraw-Hill, 1957)Google Scholar
Thomas, Laurence, “Reasons for Loving,” in The Philosophy of (Erotic) Love, ed. Robert C. Solomon and Kathleen M. Higgins (Lawrence: University of Kansas Press, 1991), 467–76Google Scholar
Toner, I. J., Moore, L. P., and Emmons, B. A., “The effects of being labeled on subsequent self-control in children,”Child Development 51 (1980): 618–21CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Torek, Paul, Something to Look Forward To: Personal Identity, Prudence, and Ethics (Ph.D. diss., University of Michigan, 1995)Google Scholar
Trzebinski, J., “Narrative Self, Understanding, and Action,” in The Self in European and North American Culture: Development and Processes, ed. A. Oosterwegel and R. A. Wicklund (Dordrecht: Kluwer, 1995), 73–88Google Scholar
Vallacher, R. R., and Wegner, D. M., A Theory of Action Identification (Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum, 1985)Google Scholar
Vallacher, R. R., and Wegner, D. M., “What Do People Think They're Doing? Action Identification and Human Behavior,”Psychological Review 94 (1987): 3–15CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Velleman, J. David, “Epistemic Freedom,”Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 70 (1989a): 73–97Google Scholar
Velleman, J. David, Practical Reflection (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1989b)Google Scholar
Velleman, J. David, “The Guise of the Good” Noûs 26 (1992a): 3–26; reprinted in his The Possibility of Practical Reason (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2000), Chapter 5Google Scholar
Velleman, J. David, “What Happens When Someone Acts?” Mind 101 (1992b): 461–81; reprinted in his The Possibility of Practical Reason (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2000), Chapter 6Google Scholar
Velleman, J. David, “The Story of Rational Action,” Philosophical Topics 21 (1993): 229–53 (1993); reprinted in his The Possibility of Practical Reason (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2000), Chapter 7Google Scholar
Velleman, J. David, “The Possibility of Practical Reason,” Ethics 106 (1996): 694–726; reprinted in his The Possibility of Practical Reason (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2000), Chapter 8Google Scholar
Velleman, J. David “Deciding How to Decide,” in Ethics and Practical Reason, ed. Garrett Cullity and Berys Gaut (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1997), 29–52; reprinted in his The Possibility of Practical Reason (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2000), Chapter 10Google Scholar
Velleman, J. David, “A Right of Self-Termination?”Ethics 109 (1999): 606–28CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Velleman, J. David, “How to Share an Intention,” in his The Possibility of Practical Reason (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2000a), Chapter 9Google Scholar
Velleman, J. David, “On the Aim of Belief,” in his The Possibility of Practical Reason (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2000b), Chapter 11Google Scholar
Velleman, J. David, The Possibility of Practical Reason (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2000c)Google Scholar
Velleman, J. David, “Narrative Explanation,”The Philosophical Review 112 (2003): 1–25CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Velleman, J. David, “Precis” and “Replies to Discussion” on The Possibility of Practical Reason, Philosophical Studies 121(2004): 225–38, 277–98Google Scholar
Vendler, Zeno, The Matter of Minds (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1984)Google Scholar
Vlastos, Gregory, “Justice and Equality,” in Social Justice, ed. Richard B. Brandt (Englewood Cliffs, N. J.: Prentice Hall, 1962), 31–72Google Scholar
Vlastos, Gregory, “The Individual as an Object of Love in Plato,” in his Platonic Studies (Princeton, N. J.: Princeton University Press, 1973), 3–42Google Scholar
Walton, Kendall L., Mimesis as Make-Believe: On the Foundations of the Representational Arts (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1993)Google Scholar
Wegner, D. M., and , Bargh J. A., “Control and Automaticity in Social Life,” in The Handbook of Social Psychology, 4th ed., Vol. 1, ed. Daniel T. Gilbert, Susan T. Fiske, and Gardner Lindzey (Boston: McGraw-Hill, 1998), 446–96Google Scholar
Wegner, D. M., and Vallacher, R. R., “Action Identification,” in Handbook of Motivation and Cognition, ed. Richard M. Sorrentino and E. Tory Higgins (New York: Guilford Press, 1986), 550–82Google Scholar
Wegner, D. M., Vallacher, R. R., Kiersted, G. W., and Dizadji, D., “Action Identification in the Emergence of Social Behavior,”Social Cognition 4 (1986): 18–38CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Weil, Simone, “Human Personality,” in The Simone Weil Reader, ed. George A. Panichas (New York: David McKay, 1977), 313–39Google Scholar
Westen, Drew, “The Superego: A Revised Developmental Model,”Journal of the American Academy of Psychoanalysis 14 (1986): 181–202CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Whiting, Jennifer, “Impersonal Friends,”Monist 74 (1991): 3–29CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wiggins, David, Identity and Spatio-Temporal Continuity (Oxford: Basic Blackwell, 1967)Google Scholar
Williams, Bernard, “A Critique of Utilitarianism,” in Utilitarianism: For and Against, J. J. C. Smart and Bernard Williams (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1973a), 75–150Google Scholar
Williams, Bernard, “Morality and the Emotions,” in his Problems of the Self (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1973b), 207–29CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Williams, Bernard, “The Imagination and the Self,” in his Problems of the Self (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1973c), 26–45CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Williams, Bernard, “The Self and the Future,” in his Problems of the Self(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1973d), 46–63
Williams, Bernard, “Internal and External Reasons,” in his Moral Luck: Philosophical Papers 19731980 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1981a), 101–13Google Scholar
Williams, Bernard, “Persons, Character and Morality,” in his Moral Luck: Philosophical Papers 1973–1980 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1981b), 1–19CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Williams, Bernard, Shame and Necessity (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1993)Google Scholar
Williams, Bernard, “Internal Reasons and the Obscurity of Blame,” in his Making Sense of Humanity and Other Philosophical Essays (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1995), 39–45CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wilson, Stephen, Feuding, Conflict, and Banditry in Nineteenth-Century Corsica (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1988)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Winnicott, D. W., “Ego Distortion in Terms of True and False Self,” in Collected Papers: Through Paediatrics to Psycho-analysis (London: Tavistock Publications, 1958)Google Scholar
Winnicott, D. W., “Hate in the Countertransference,” Through Paediatrics to Psycho-analysis (London: Hogarth Press, 1975), 194–203Google Scholar
Winnicott, D. W., “Mirror-Role of Mother and Family in Child Development,” in his Playing and Reality (New York: Routledge, 1989), 111–18Google Scholar
Wittgenstein, Ludwig, The Blue and Brown Books (Oxford: Blackwell, 1972)Google Scholar
Wolf, Susan, “Moral Saints,”Journal of Philosophy 79 (1982): 419–39CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wolf, Susan, “Morality and Partiality,”Philosophical Perspectives 6 (1992): 243–59CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wolff, Robert Paul, “There's Nobody Here but Us Persons,” in Women and Philosophy: Toward a Theory of Liberation, ed. Carol C. Gould and Marx W. Wartofsky (New York: G. P. Putnam's Sons, 1976), 128–144Google Scholar
Wollheim, Richard, “Imagination and Identification,” in his On Art and the Mind (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1974), 54–83Google Scholar
Wollheim, Richard, The Thread of Life (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1984)Google Scholar
Wollheim, Richard, Painting as an Art (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1987)Google Scholar
Wollheim, Richard, On the Emotions (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1999)Google Scholar
Yeats, W. B., “For Anne Gregory,” in The Collected Poems of W. B. Yeats (New York: Macmillan, 1956), p. 240Google Scholar
Zanna, M. P., and Cooper, J., “Dissonance and the pill: An attribution approach to studying the arousal properties of dissonance,”Journal of Personality & Social Psychology 29 (1974): 703–709CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Zanna, M. P., Higgins, E. T., and Taves, P. A., “Is dissonance phenomenologically aversive?”Journal of Experimental Social Psychology 12 (1976): 530–538CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Zillman, D., “Attribution and misattribution of excitatory reactions,” New Directions in Attribution Research, Vol. 2, ed. John H. Harvey, William Ickes, and Robert F. Kidd (Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum, 1978), 335–68Google Scholar
Zillman, E., Johnson, R. C., and Day, K. D., “Attribution of apparent arousal and proficiency of recovery for sympathetic activation affecting excitation transfer to aggressive behavior,”Journal of Experimental Social Psychology 10 (1974): 503–15CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

  • Bibliography
  • J. David Velleman, New York University
  • Book: Self to Self
  • Online publication: 21 July 2009
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511498862.015
Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

  • Bibliography
  • J. David Velleman, New York University
  • Book: Self to Self
  • Online publication: 21 July 2009
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511498862.015
Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

  • Bibliography
  • J. David Velleman, New York University
  • Book: Self to Self
  • Online publication: 21 July 2009
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511498862.015
Available formats
×