Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-76fb5796d-x4r87 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-29T07:42:14.235Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

13 - Political Philosophy and Prosecutorial Power

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  31 July 2009

Francis J. Mootz III
Affiliation:
University of the Pacific, California
Get access

Summary

Much recent scholarship has been animated by the desire to understand the limits of law and how law figures its own limits. It has charted the gaps, fissures, and incompleteness of legality in a society whose political rhetoric stresses the depth and strength of our commitment to the rule of law. This work is enlivened and enriched when it is rooted in, or informed by, the perspectives of political philosophy.

Karl Llewellyn (1934: 205) was correct in identifying ways philosophy shapes legal action and noting that “[p]hilosophers' writings and law-men's doings meet rarely on the same level of discourse, and part of the game is to find out where they do, where they do not, and – if you can – the why of either.” However, the relevance of philosophical perspectives to law was, and is, broader than Llewellyn acknowledged. His invitation to examine what he variously called “philosophy-in-action” or “implicit philosophy” so as to identify the “implicit” and “unthought” premises of legal action pointed to that broader relevance even if he did not himself pursue it (Llewellyn 1934: 206). In what follows we take up Llewellyn's invitation, using political philosophy to cast new light on the work of one kind of “law man” – prosecutors – and, in so doing, to chart another domain of what Sarat and Hussain (2004: 1311) have called “lawful lawlessness.”

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2009

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Agamben, Giorgio. Homo Sacer: Sovereign Power and Bare Life. Stanford, CA: Stanford Univ. Press, 1998.Google Scholar
Agamben, Giorgio. State of Exception. Chicago: Univ. of Chicago Press, 2005.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Blackstone, William. Commentaries on the Laws of England. New York: Harper, 1850.Google Scholar
Connolly, William. “The Ethos of Sovereignty.” In Law and the Sacred. Eds. Sarat, Austin, Douglas, Lawrence, and Umphrey, Martha. Palo Alto, CA: Stanford Univ. Press, 2006.Google Scholar
Davis, Angela J.The American Prosecutor: Independence, Power, and the Threat of Tyranny.” Iowa L. Rev. 86.2 (2001): 393–465.Google Scholar
Davis v. United States, 512 U.S. 452 (1994).
Ely, Amie N.Prosecutorial Discretion as an Ethical Necessity: The Ashcroft Memorandum's Curtailment of the Prosecutor's Duty to ‘Seek Justice.’Cornell L. Rev. 90.1 (2004): 237–78.Google Scholar
Jackson, Robert H.The Federal Prosecutor.” J. Am. Judicature Soc'y 24 (June, 1940): 18–20.Google Scholar
Kadish, Mortimer, and Sanford, Kadish. Discretion to Disobey. Palo Alto, CA: Stanford Univ. Press, 1973.Google Scholar
Llewellyn, Karl. “On Philosophy in American Law,” U. Pa. L. Rev. 82.3 (1934): 205–12.Google Scholar
Locke, John. The Second Treatise on Civil Government. Amherst, NY: Prometheus Books, 1986.Google Scholar
Loewenstein, Andrew B.Judicial Review and the Limits of Prosecutorial Discretion.” Am. Crim. L. Rev. 38.2 (2001): 351–72.Google Scholar
Montesquieu, Baron. The Spirit of the Laws. New York: Hafner Publishing, 1949.Google Scholar
Sarat, Austin, and Nasser, Hussain. “On Lawful Lawlessness: George Ryan and the Rhetoric of Sparing Life.” Stan. L. Rev. 56.5 (2004): 1307–44.Google Scholar
Schmitt, Carl. Political Theology. Chicago: Univ. of Chicago Press, 1985.Google Scholar
Vorenberg, JamesDecent Restraint of Prosecutorial Power.” Harv. L. Rev. 94.7 (1981): 1521–73.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×