We use cookies to distinguish you from other users and to provide you with a better experience on our websites. Close this message to accept cookies or find out how to manage your cookie settings.
To save content items to your account,
please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies.
If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account.
Find out more about saving content to .
To save content items to your Kindle, first ensure no-reply@cambridge.org
is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings
on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part
of your Kindle email address below.
Find out more about saving to your Kindle.
Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations.
‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi.
‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.
This paper investigates the Confucian conception of political responsibility as a political virtue essential for an ordinary non-Confucian ruler's actualization of humane government by paying close attention to the early Confucian discourses of Heaven and disaster. After briefly discussing Confucius's seminal idea of responsibility, this paper shows how Mencius developed the political conception of responsibility, as a noncausal responsibility shared by the ruler and the virtuous ministers for a humane government, especially under the condition of natural disasters. It then discusses how the Han Confucian philosopher Dong Zhongshu reformulated the Mencian theory of responsibility and humane government under radically altered political circumstances by advancing a new version of Confucianism, central to which is the causal conception of political responsibility. This paper concludes by discussing how the evolution of Confucian political theory from Mencius to Dong Zhongshu should be understood with a view to the question of political legitimacy.
In recent years, Confucian philosophers have vigorously explored the ideal of human dignity by reinterpreting key classical Confucian texts, giving rise to two contending accounts of human dignity: egalitarian dignity versus meritocratic dignity. Meritocratic dignity understands human dignity as an achievement, the outcome of a long process of moral self-cultivation, while egalitarian dignity, inspired by Mencius who believes that human nature is good, disagrees with the strong virtue-ethical account of human dignity and shift attention to universal moral potentiality. After showing that each Confucian account underpins a distinctive political system – Confucian constitutional democracy and Confucian political meritocracy, respectively – this chapter attempts to reinforce the egalitarian account of Confucian dignity from the standpoint of Xunzian Confucianism predicated on the assumption that human nature is bad. The chapter argues that, whereas meritocratc dignity is limited in justifying the independent judiciary and protecting citizens’ rights, egalitarian dignity can coherently undergird the principle of the separation of power and the right to political participation.
This Element aims to critically examine the philosophical thought of Im Yunjidang 任允摯堂 (1721–93), a female Korean Neo-Confucian philosopher from the Chosŏn 朝鮮 dynasty (1392–1910), and to present her as a feminist thinker. Unlike most Korean women of her time, Yunjidang had the exceptional opportunity to be introduced to a major philosophical debate among Korean Neo-Confucians, which was focused on two core questions-whether sages and commoners share the same heart-mind, and whether the natures of human beings and animals are identical. In the course of engaging in this debate, she was able to reformulate Neo-Confucian metaphysics and ethics of moral self-cultivation, culminating in her bold ideas of the moral equality between men and women and the possibility of female sagehood. By proposing a 'stage-approach' to feminism that is also sensitive to the cultural context, this Element shows that Yunjidang's philosophical thought could be best captured in terms of Confucian feminism.
Confucianism is sometimes understood as an ethical system that consciously opposes the pursuit of material interest. The opening page of the Mengzi is most telling in this regard: upon King Hui of Liang’s question of how to make his state profitable, the quintessential political question that no sensible political leader can afford to avoid, Mencius responds, “Why must you mention the word ‘profit’ (he bi yue li* 何必曰利)? All that matters is that there should be ren and yi.”
One of my core arguments in previous chapters has been that the different modes of Confucian virtue politics advanced by Mencius and Xunzi (virtue constitutionalism versus ritual constitutionalism in particular and negative Confucianism versus positive Confucianism to a lesser degree) are closely connected with the classical Confucians’ contrasting accounts of human nature and moral self-cultivation.
In Chapter 2, I argued that Mencius’s and Xunzi’s contrasting attitudes toward the abdication doctrine, and, more importantly, their differing visions of Confucian constitutionalism, ultimately have to do with their differing conceptualizations of kingship – personal (Mencius) and institutional (Xunzi).
In this book, I have examined how Mencius and Xunzi developed two different, though related, versions of Confucian virtue politics under new political circumstances ushered in by the rise of independent and sovereign states during the Warring States period. That is, I argued, in their struggle to adapt the Confucian paradigm of virtue politics to the political context of the warring states, which I have reconstructed as consisting of four key propositions – the virtue proposition, the virtue politics proposition, the moral education proposition, and the material condition proposition – they radically innovated the content of Confucian virtue politics while expanding its scope by developing political theories from their foundational assumptions of human nature (good or bad) and thus in a way very consistent with their contrasting accounts of moral self-cultivation (developmental or re-formational).
In the past two decades, Confucian political theory has rapidly established itself as one of the most vigorous subfields of political theory, obliterating the image of Confucianism as a relic of the “feudal” age and the single greatest obstacle to East Asia’s modernization. Of course, Confucianism as a set of intellectual ideas or as a world religion has long been incorporated into modern education since East Asia’s full-scale “encounter with the West” in the late nineteenth century.
In the previous chapter, we noted that there are two dimensions of Confucian virtue politics – positive and negative – and Xunzi brought Mencius’s underdeveloped idea of positive Confucianism to full fruition by actively expounding upon the critical role that material interest can play in creating and maintaining the Confucian civil political order.
In the Confucian political tradition, badao (the Way of the hegemon) is commonly identified as the mode of statecraft that is squarely opposed to the Kingly Way, the ideal statecraft that relies on virtue and ritual, allegedly practiced by the ancient sage-kings.