Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-nmvwc Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-06-17T06:03:13.493Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false
This chapter is part of a book that is no longer available to purchase from Cambridge Core

11 - Phenomenology: returning to the things themselves

from PART II - METHOD

James Chase
Affiliation:
University of Tasmania
Get access

Summary

The tradition of phenomenology has proved remarkably resilient, enduring throughout the entirety of the twentieth century and beyond. In fact, it continues to be one of the primary research fronts of contemporary continental philosophy (both on the European continent and beyond), as well as a tradition that many of the great continental philosophers have aligned themselves with – Husserl, Edith Stein, Heidegger, Sartre, Merleau-Ponty, Levinas, Ricoeur, Gadamer, Arendt, Derrida, Henry, Marion and so on – while also reinventing in more or less radical ways. In recent times, the term phenomenology also crops up repeatedly in analytic philosophy of mind where it roughly designates the qualitative character of experience, or what are sometimes called qualia. Of course, in Husserl and the tradition stemming from him, phenomenology has come to mean something rather more specific than merely a term that is interchangeable with “what it is like”. By the same token, if we describe phenomenology as a descriptive method for studying and reflecting on experience and its variegated structures, it is not radically divorced from some important analytic concerns either, and it is perhaps for this reason that philosophers such as Ryle and Austin (and the early pragmatist, C. S. Peirce) have sometimes wondered whether their own projects might best be called phenomenological.

It seems to be phenomenology's more grandiose methodological aspirations that analytic philosophers have been troubled by, rather than any kind of wholesale rejection of the worth of all phenomenological description (although there have been wholesale rejections too).

Type
Chapter
Information
Analytic versus Continental
Arguments on the Method and Value of Philosophy
, pp. 115 - 129
Publisher: Acumen Publishing
Print publication year: 2010

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×