Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-8448b6f56d-m8qmq Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-20T01:09:16.547Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

11 - Syncategoremata, exponibilia, sophismata

from IV - Logic in the high middle ages: semantic theory

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  28 March 2008

Get access

Summary

A grammatical distinction between categoremata and syncategoremata

The paradigm of the categorical proposition with which medieval logicians were primarily concerned is a sentence of two words that serve as the subject term and the predicate term – e.g., ‘Socrates currit.’ Any word that can be used alone as a subject term or as a predicate term is classifiable as a categorematic word; all other words are classifiable as syncategorematic words, those that can occur in a proposition, whether categorical or hypothetical, only along with at least one properly matched pair of categorematic words – e.g., ‘Solus Socrates currit,’ ‘Socrates currit contingenter’, ‘Socrates non currit’, “Si Socrates currit, Socrates movetur.’ Drawing the distinction between categoremata and syncategoremata along this line, which seems to have been the original line of distinction, produces mutually exclusive and jointly exhaustive classes that coincide almost perfectly with certain groupings of the parts of speech (parts orationis) recognized by medieval grammarians: the names (both substantival and adjectivel), the personal and demonstrative pronouns and the verbs (excluding auxiliary verbs); the syncategoremate are all the others – e.g., the conjunction adverbs, and prepositions.

The logicians' notion of syncategoremata

The notice of synacategoremata that became important in medieval logic was, however, both narrower and broader than that comparatively orderly classification in terms of the parts of speech. Although more than fifty different words were considered in one or another medieval logicians' treatment of syncategoremate, by no means all non categorematic words in even the relatively small classes, such as conjunctions, were of enough interest to the logicians to be treated expressly among their syncategoremata.

Type
Chapter
Information
The Cambridge History of Later Medieval Philosophy
From the Rediscovery of Aristotle to the Disintegration of Scholasticism, 1100–1600
, pp. 211 - 245
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 1982

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Albert, Saxony (1502). Sophismata, ParisGoogle Scholar
Albert, Saxony (1522). Perutilis logica, VeniceGoogle Scholar
Ashworth, E.J. (1973). ‘The Doctrine of Exponibilia in the Fifteenth and Sixteenth Centuries’, Vivarium 11:.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Boehner, Philotheus (1952). Medieval Logic: An Outline of Its Development from 1250–c. 1400, Manchester University PressGoogle Scholar
Braakhuis, H. A. G. (1977). ‘The Views of William of Sherwood on Some Semantical Topics and Their Relation to Those of Roger Bacon’, Vivarium 15: (1978).Google Scholar
Braakhuis, H. A. G. (1978).I De Ontwikkeling van de theorie van de syncategoremata tot aan de 13de eeuw; II. De 13de eeuwse syncategoremata-tractaten; III. Enkele aspecten van de ontwikkeling van de theorie van de syncategoremata in de ljde eeuw. Typescript; preliminary versionGoogle Scholar
Braakhuis, H. A. G. (1978a). Preliminary editions of Robert Bacon (?), Sincategoreumata, and Henry of Ghent, Sincathegoreumata, Typescript; preliminary versionGoogle Scholar
Braakhuis, H. A. G. (1979) De 13de eeuwse Tractaten over syncategorematische Termen (Deel I: Inleidende studie; Deel II: Uitgave van Nicolaas van Parijs' Sincategoreumata), Krips Repro MeppelGoogle Scholar
Geach, P. T. (1961). Reference and Generality, Cornell University PressGoogle Scholar
Grabmann, Martin (1940a). Die Sophismataliteratur des 12. und 13. Jahrhunderts mit Textausgabe eines Sophisma des Boethius von Dacien (BGPM, XXXVI, 1), AschendorffGoogle Scholar
Kretzmann, Norman (1966). William of Sherwood's Introduction to Logic, University of Minnesota PressGoogle Scholar
Kretzmann, Norman (1968). William of Sherwood's Treatise on Syncategorematic Words, University of Minnesota PressGoogle Scholar
Kretzmann, Norman (1970). ‘Medieval Logicians on the Meaning of the Propositio’, Journal of Philosophy 67:CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kretzmann, Norman (1976). ‘Incipit/Desinit’ in Machamer, P. and Turnbull, R. (eds.) Motion and Time, Space and Matter, Ohio State University PressGoogle Scholar
Kretzmann, Norman (1977). ‘Socrates is Whiter than Plato Begins to be White’, Noûs II:Google Scholar
Mullally, Joseph P. (1964). Peter of Spain: Tractatus Syncategorematum and Selected Anonymous Treatises, Marquette University PressGoogle Scholar
Nuchelmans, Gabriel (1973). Theories of the Proposition: Ancient and Medieval Conceptions of the Bearers of Truth and Falsity (North-Holland Linguistic Series, 8), North-HollandGoogle Scholar
O'Donnell, J. Reginald ed. (1941). ‘The Syncategoremata of William of Sherwood’, Mediaeval Studies 3:.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Paul, Venice (1493a). Quadratura, VeniceGoogle Scholar
Paul, Venice (1493b). Sophismata, VeniceGoogle Scholar
Paul, Venice (1499). Logica magna, VeniceGoogle Scholar
Peter, Spain (1489). Textus omnium tractatuum Petri Hispani etiam sincathegreumatum et parvorum logicalium cum copulatis secundum doctrinam divi Thome Aquinatis iuxta processum magistrorum Colonic in bursa Montis regentium, CologneGoogle Scholar
Peter, Spain (1964). Tractatus syncategorematum and Selected Anonymous Treatises, tr. Mullally, J. P., with an introduction by Mullally, J. P. and Houde, R. (Mediaeval Texts in Translation, 13), Marquette University PressGoogle Scholar
Pinborg, Jan (1972). Logik und Semantik im Mittelalter — Ein Überblick (Problemata, 10), Frommann-HolzboogGoogle Scholar
Pinborg, Jan (1975a). ‘Die Logik der Modistae’, Studia Mediewistyczne 16:.Google Scholar
Pinborg, Jan (1976c). ‘Magister Abstractionum’, CIMAGL 18:.Google Scholar
Priscian, (1855–9). Institutionsgrammaticae, ed. Hertz, Martin (Grammatici Latini), Teubner (Reprinted Georg Olms 1961)Google Scholar
Pseudo-Petrus, (1489). Tractatus exponibilium in Spain, Peter (1489)Google Scholar
Rijk, L. M. ed. (1962–7). Logica modernorum: A contribution to the History of Early Terminist Logic. I: On the Twelfth Century Theories of Fallacy (1962); II, 1: The Origin and Early Development of the Theory of Supposition; II, 2: Texts and Indices (1967), Van GorcumGoogle Scholar
Rijk, L. M. ed. (1972). Peter of Spain (Petrus Hispanus Portugalensis) Tractatus called afterwards ‘Summule Logicales’, Van GorcumGoogle Scholar
William, Heytesbury (1494c). Sophismata in Heytesbury, William 1494a.Google Scholar
William, Ockham (1974a). Opera philosophica [OP] I: Summa logicae, ed. Boehner, P., Gál, G., and Brown, S., in Ockham, William 1967–Google Scholar
Wilson, Curtis(1956). William Heytesbury: Medieval Logic and the Rise of Mathematical Physics (Publications in Medieval Science, 3), University of Wisconsin PressGoogle Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×