Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-m9kch Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-05-21T08:49:25.712Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

58 - From intuitionism to emotivism

from 14 - Ethics, religion, and the arts

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  28 March 2008

Jonathan Dancy
Affiliation:
University of Reading
Thomas Baldwin
Affiliation:
University of York
Get access

Summary

Moral philosophy during the period under review was marked by the dominance in England of a form of ethical intuitionism that arose in response to G. E. Moore’s Principia Ethica (1903). By the mid-1930s this began to be challenged, both in England and in the United States, by various forms of emotivism. In some isolation from this debate, Dewey continued to write extensively on ethics.

INTUITIONISM

The intuitionist school consisted of H. A. Prichard, W.D. Ross, H.W. B. Joseph, and E. F. Carritt in Oxford and C. D. Broad and A. C. Ewing in Cambridge. Prichard should probably be considered the leader of the school, though he published the least; Broad called Prichard ‘a man of immense ability whom I have always regarded as the Oxford Moore’ (1971: 14).

The intuitionists believed that rightness and goodness were distinct qualities, qualities that such things as people, actions, emotions, motives, intentions, and consequences could have. They were interested in the nature of and relation between these two qualities and in the distinction between intrinsic and extrinsic forms of them, and in which things in fact have these properties. Ross, for instance, argued that there was no such thing as instrumental goodness, that is, value as a means (1930: 133, 1939: 257); but he insisted that there was such a thing as intrinsic value, and that it was distinct from intrinsic rightness. Further, nothing was capable of being both intrinsically good and intrinsically right (Prichard 1912: 5–6).

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2003

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Ayer, A. J. (1936). Language, Truth and Logic, London: Gollancz.Google Scholar
Barnes, W. H. F. (1934). ‘A Suggestion about Values’, Analysis 1.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Barnes, W. H. F. (1948). ‘Ethics without Propositions’, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, supp. vol. XXII.Google Scholar
Braithwaite, R. B. (1928). ‘Verbal Ambiguity and Philosophical Analysis’, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 28.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Broad, C. D. (1928). ‘Analysis of Some Ethical Concepts’, Journal of Philosophical Studies (Philosophy) 3; reprinted in Broad, 1971.Google Scholar
Broad, C. D. (1930). Five Types of Ethical Theory, London: Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
Broad, C. D. (1934). ‘Is “Goodness” a Name of a Simple Non-Natural Quality?’, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 34; reprinted in Broad, 1971.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Broad, C. D. (1945). ‘Some Reflections on Moral-Sense Theories in Ethics’, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 45; reprinted in Broad, 1971.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Broad, C. D. (1971). Broad’s Critical Essays in Moral Philosophy, ed. Cheney, D., London: George Allen and Unwin.Google Scholar
Carnap, R. (1935). Philosophy and Logical Syntax, London: Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
Carritt, E. F. (1928). The Theory of Morals, London: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Carritt, E. F. (1935). Morals and Politics, London: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Carritt, E. F. (1947). Ethical and Political Thinking, Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Dewey, J. and Tufts, J. H. (1932). Ethics, rev. edn, New York: Holt (Later Works, vol. VII).Google Scholar
Dewey, J. (1899–1924). The Middle Works: 1899–1924, 15 vols., ed. Boyston, J. A., Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press (1976–83).Google Scholar
Dewey, J. (1922). Human Nature and Conduct, New York: Holt (Middle Works, vol. XIV).Google Scholar
Dewey, J. (1925–53). The Later Works: 1925–1953, 17 vols., ed. Boyston, J. A., Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press (1976–83).Google Scholar
Dewey, J. (1929). The Quest for Certainty, New York: Milton, Balch and Co. (Later Works, vol. IV).Google Scholar
Dewey, J. (1939). The Theory of Valuation, Chicago: University of Chicago Press (Later Works, vol. XIII).Google Scholar
Edwards, P. (1955). The Logic of Moral Discourse, Glencoe, IL: The Free Press.Google Scholar
Ewing, A. C. (1929). The Morality of Punishment, London: Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
Ewing, A. C. (1947). The Definition of Good, London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Ewing, A. C. (1953). Ethics, London: English Universities Press, Teach Yourself Books.Google Scholar
Ewing, A. C. (1959). Second Thoughts in Moral Philosophy, London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Festenstein, M. (1997). Pragmatism and Political Theory, Oxford: Polity.Google Scholar
Gouinlock, J. (1972). John Dewey’s Philosophy of Value, New York: Humanities Press.Google Scholar
Hägerström, A. (1911). ‘Om Moraliska Föreställningars Sanning’. Trans. 1964 Sandin, R. T., Philosophy and Religion, London: George Allen and Unwin.Google Scholar
Hägerström, A. (1938). Inquiries into the Nature of Laws and Morals, trans. Broad, C. D., Stockholm: Almqvist and Wiksell.Google Scholar
Hurley, P. E. (1988). ‘Dewey on Desires: The Lost Argument’, Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 24.Google Scholar
Joseph, H. W. B. (1931). Some Problems in Ethics, Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Mackie, J. L. (1946). ‘A Refutation of Morals’, Australian Journal of Psychology and Philosophy 24: 77f.Google Scholar
Moore, G. E. (1903). Principia Ethica, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press; rev. edn, ed. Baldwin, T. 1993.Google Scholar
Moore, G. E. (1912). Ethics, London: Home University Library.Google Scholar
Moore, G. E. (1952). ‘A Reply to my Critics’ in Schilpp, P. A. ed., The Philosophy of G. E. Moore, New York: Tudor Publishing Co..Google Scholar
Ogden, C. K. and Richards, I. A. (1923). The Meaning of Meaning, London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Prichard, H. A. (1912). ‘Does Moral Philosophy Rest on a Mistake?’, Mind 21. Repr. in Prichard, 1968.Google Scholar
Prichard, H. A. (1928). ‘Duty and Interest’; inaugural lecture, repr. in Prichard, 1968.Google Scholar
Prichard, H. A. (1932). ‘Duty and Ignorance of Fact’, Proceedings of the British Academy; repr. with endnotes in Prichard, 1968.Google Scholar
Prichard, H. A. (1968). Moral Obligation, ed. Urmson, J. O., Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Rashdall, H. (1907). The Theory of Good and Evil, Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Robinson, R. (1948). ‘The Emotive Theory of Ethics’, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, supp. vol. XXII.Google Scholar
Ross, W. D. (1930). The Right and The Good, Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Ross, W. D. (1939). Foundations of Ethics, Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Russell, B. A. W. (1936). Religion and Science, New York: Holt.Google Scholar
Selby-Bigge, L. A. (1897). British Moralists, Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Stevenson, C. L. (1937). ‘The Emotive Meaning of Ethical Terms’, Mind 46. Repr. in Stevenson, 1963.Google Scholar
Stevenson, C. L. (1938). ‘Persuasive Definitions’, Mind 47. Repr. in Stevenson, 1963.Google Scholar
Stevenson, C. L. (1944). Ethics and Language, Yale: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Stevenson, C. L. (1948). ‘The Nature of Ethical Disagreement’, Sigma. Repr. in Stevenson, 1963. This piece was written in 1941.Google Scholar
Stevenson, C. L. (1963). Facts and Values, New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Stratton, G. M. (1903). ‘A Psychological Test of Virtue’, International Journal of Ethics 11.Google Scholar
Urmson, J. O. (1968). The Emotive Theory of Ethics, London: Hutchinson.Google Scholar
Urmson, J. O. (1975). ‘A Defence of Intuitionism’, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 75.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Welchman, J. (1995). Dewey’s Ethical Thought, Ithaca: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Wittgenstein, L. (1921). Logische-philosophische Abhandlung, in Annalen der Natur Philosophie. Trans. 1961 Pears, D. F. and McGuinness, B. F., Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus, London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Wittgenstein, L. (1965). ‘Lecture on Ethics’, Philosophical Review 74.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×