Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-8448b6f56d-xtgtn Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-24T01:42:57.960Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

5 - Proposition and judgement

from II - Logic, language, and abstract objects

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  28 March 2008

Daniel Garber
Affiliation:
University of Chicago
Michael Ayers
Affiliation:
University of Oxford
Get access

Summary

CATEGORICAL PROPOSITIONS

Seventeenth-century logicians commonly adhered to the usual distinction between two operations of the mind: on the one hand, simple conceptions, through which things are apprehended that, as categorematic terms, are capable of becoming the subject and the predicate of a categorical proposition; on the other, acts of predication, by which the contents of simple apprehensions are combined into a propositional complex that is a suitable potential object of assent or dissent. Although at the propositional level acts of predication and judgement will often coincide, authors were aware that there are good reasons to distinguish merely apprehensive propositions from judicative propositions. The former are states of affairs that are presented to the mind without any commitment to truth or falsity, whereas the latter actually have judicative or assertive force. Notwithstanding the predominant tendency to stick to the traditional division into incomplex concepts and propositional complexes, there were also factors at work which made for blurring of that fundamental distinction. One of them was Descartes's use of the word idea for both the categorematic elements of a proposition and the proposition itself, as the object of judgement. Spinoza went even farther by explicitly declaring that at bottom a particular idea and a particular act of affirming or denying are one and the same thing. When, for example, the mind affirms that the sum of the three angles of a triangle is equal to two right angles, that affirmation cannot exist or be thought without the idea of a triangle.

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2000

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Du Trieu, Philippe, in his Manuductio ad logicam of 1614 (Du Trieu, 1826, II, 1, 2, 2), and Geulincx, (Geulincx 1891–3, vol. I)
Malebranche, Recherche de la vérité of 1674
Risse, De augementis scientiarum 1964–70, vol. I.

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×