Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-76fb5796d-45l2p Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-25T16:02:08.387Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Section I - Transition from common to philosophic moral cognition of reason

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  24 February 2010

Jens Timmermann
Affiliation:
University of St Andrews, Scotland
Get access

Summary

Kant presupposes what he takes to be the central belief about the nature of value that, at least implicitly, is universally acknowledged to be true: only a good will is good absolutely and without restriction. However, an analysis of the nature of goodness does not advance the project of grounding a new moral philosophy. Any substantive conception of value leads to what Kant later calls ‘heteronomy’: causal regularities that help us to realise a pre-given end, not to a formal law that first defines moral value. That is why he switches to analysing the cognate concept of duty. The discussion of clear cases of action ‘from duty’ – the suicidal person who nevertheless preserves his life, the beneficent act of someone not naturally sympathetic, the gout sufferer who still takes care of his long-term well-being – reveals that duty is characterised by a certain robustness in the face of opposing inclination. Actions have moral value only if they are done from duty; and duty is defined as the necessity of an action from reverence for ‘the law’.

What kind of law can this be? Kant claims to have shown that it must be purely formal, because the matter of willing – its intention or purpose – has been shown to be morally immaterial. He proceeds to give a first formulation of the supreme principle of all moral action, illustrated only briefly by means of the example of a lying promise and not yet christened with its official name, the ‘categorical imperative’.

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2007

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Ameriks, Karl. ‘Kant on the Good Will’, in Interpreting Kant's Critiques, 193–211 (Clarendon Press, 2003; first published in 1989)Google Scholar
Baron, Marcia. Kantian Ethics almost without Apology (Cornell University Press, 1995)Google Scholar
Baron, Marcia. ‘Acting from Duty’, in Immanuel Kant. Groundwork for the Metaphysics of Morals, trans. Wood, Allen (Yale University Press, 2002), 92–110Google Scholar
Benson, Paul. ‘Moral Worth’, Philosophical Studies 51 (1987), 365–82CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Henson, Richard. ‘What Kant Might Have Said: Moral Worth and the Overdetermination of Dutiful Action’, Philosophical Review 88 (1979), 39–54CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Herman, Barbara. ‘On the Value of Acting from the Motive of Duty’, in The Practice of Moral Judgment (Harvard University Press, 1993), 1–22 (first published in 1981)Google Scholar
Johnson, Robert. ‘Expressing a Good Will: Kant on the Motive of Duty’, Southern Journal of Philosophy 34 (1996), 147–68CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Korsgaard, Christine. ‘Kant's Analysis of Obligation: The Argument of Groundwork I’, in Creating the Kingdom of Ends (Cambridge University Press, 1996), 43–76 (first published in 1989)Google Scholar
Korsgaard, Christine ‘Two Distinctions in Goodness’, in Creating the Kingdom of Ends (Cambridge University Press, 1996), 249–74 (first published in 1983)
Potter, Nelson. ‘The Argument of Kant's Groundwork, Chapter I’, in Kant's Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals, ed. Guyer, P. (Rowman & Littlefield, 1998), 29–49 (first published in 1974)Google Scholar
Rickless, Samuel C.‘From the Good Will to the Formula of Universal Law’, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 68 (2004), 554–77CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schönecker, Dieter. ‘What is the “First Proposition” Regarding Duty in Kant's Grundlegung?’, in Kant und die Berliner Aufklärung, ed. Gerhardt, V., Horstmann, R.-P. and Schumacher, R. (De Gruyter, 2001), vol. III, 89–95CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stocker, Michael. ‘The Schizophrenia of Modern Ethical Theories’, Journal of Philosophy 73 (1976), 453–66CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stratton-Lake, Philip. Kant, Duty and Moral Worth (Routledge, 2000)Google Scholar
Timmermann, Jens. ‘Good but not Required? Assessing the Demands of Kantian Ethics’, Journal of Moral Philosophy 2 (2005), 9–28CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Walker, Ralph C. S. ‘Achtung in the Grundlegung’, in Grundlegung zur Metaphysik der Sitten, ed. Höffe, O. (Klostermann, 1993), 97–116Google Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×