Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-76fb5796d-skm99 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-26T10:28:33.463Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Bibliography

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 September 2016

Carl Gillett
Affiliation:
Northern Illinois University
Get access

Summary

Image of the first page of this content. For PDF version, please use the ‘Save PDF’ preceeding this image.'
Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2016

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Aizawa, K. 2007: “The Biochemistry of Memory Consolidation: A Model System for the Philosophy of Mind.” Synthese, 155, pp. 6598.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Aizawa, K., and Gillett, C. 2009a: “Levels, Individual Variation and Massive Multiple Realization in Neurobiology.” In Bickle (2009), pp. 539–81.Google Scholar
Aizawa, K., & Gillett, C. 2009b: “The (Multiple) Realization of Psychological and Other Properties in the Sciences.” Mind & Language, 24(2), pp. 181208.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Aizawa, K., & Gillett, C. 2011: “The Autonomy of Psychology in the Age of Neuroscience.” In McKay Illari, P., Russo, F., and Williamson, J. (eds.), Causality in the Sciences. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Aizawa, K., & Gillett, C. (eds.) 2016: Scientific Composition and Metaphysical Ground. London: Palgrave MacMillan.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Aizawa, K., & Gillett, C. Forthcoming: The Parts of Sciences: Scientific Composition and Compositional Explanation. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Aizawa, K., & Gillett, C. Unpublished: “Multiple Realization and Methodology in Neuroscience and Psychology.”Google Scholar
Alexander, S. 1920: Space, Time and Deity. 2 vols. The Gifford Lectures 1916–18. Toronto: Macmillan.Google Scholar
Anderson, P. 1972: “More is Different: Broken Symmetry and the Nature of the Hierarchical Structure of Science.” Science, 177, pp. 393–6.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Anderson, P. 1990: “Solid-State Experimentalists: Theory Should Be on Tap, Not on Top.” Physics Today, 43(9), pp. 911.Google Scholar
Anderson, P. 1995: “Historical Overview of the Twentieth Century in Physics.” In Brown, Pais, and Pippard (1995), vol. 3, pp. 2017–33.Google Scholar
Andersen, P., Christiansen, P., Emmeche, C., and Finnemann, N. (eds.) 2000: Downward Causation: Minds, Bodies and Matter. Aarhus: Aarhus University Press.Google Scholar
Armstrong, D.M. 1997: A World of States of Affairs. New York: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Atkins, P. 1995: “The Limitless Power of Science.” In Cornwell (ed.) (1995), pp. 122–31.Google Scholar
Atmanspacher, H., and Bishop, R. 2006: “Contextual Emergence in the Description of Properties.” Foundations of Physics, 36, pp. 1753–77.Google Scholar
Auyang, S. 1998: Foundations of Complex-Systems Theories in Economics, Evolutionary Biology, and Statistical Physics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ayala, F., and Arp, R. (eds.) 2009: Contemporary Debates in Philosophy of Biology. Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ayala, F., and Dobzhansky, T. (eds.) 1974: Studies in the Philosophy of Biology: Reduction and Related Problems. New York: Macmillan.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bechtel, W., and Mundale, J. 1999: “Multiple Realizability Revisited.” Philosophy of Science, v.66, pp. 175207.Google Scholar
Bechtel, W., and Richardson, R. 1993: Discovering Complexity. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Beckermann, A., Flohr, H., and Kim, J. (eds.) 1992: Emergence or Reduction? New York: de Gruyter.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bedau, M. 1997: “Weak Emergence.” Philosophical Perspectives, 11, pp. 375–99.Google Scholar
Bedau, M. 2002: “Downward Causation and the Autonomy of Weak Emergence.” Principia, 6, pp. 550.Google Scholar
Bedau, M. 2008: “Is Weak Emergence Just in the Mind?Minds and Machines, 18, pp. 443–59.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bennett, K. 2003: “Why the Exclusion Problem Seems Intractable, and How, Just Maybe, to Tract it.” Noûs, 37(3), pp. 471–97.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bennett, K. 2011: “Construction Area: No Hard Hat Required.” Philosophical Studies, 154, pp. 79104.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bennett, K., and McLaughlin, B. 2005: “Supervenience.” The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. <http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2003/entries/supervenience/>..>Google Scholar
Bertalanffy, V. 1950: “An Outline of General System Theory.” British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 1, pp. 134–65.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bickle, J. 1998: Psychoneural Reduction: The New Wave. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Bickle, J. 2003: Philosophy and Neuroscience: A Ruthlessly Reductive Account. Boston: Kluwer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bickle, J. 2006: “Reducing Mind to Molecular Pathways.” Synthese, v.151, pp. 411–34CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bickle, J. 2008: “Real Reduction in Real Neuroscience: Metascience, Not Philosophy of Science (and Certainly Not Metaphysics!).” In Hohwy and Kallestrup (2008), pp. 34–51.Google Scholar
Bickle, J. (ed.) 2009: The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy and Neuroscience. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bishop, R. 2005: “Patching Physics and Chemistry Together.” Philosophy of Science, 72, pp. 710–22.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bishop, R. 2006a: “The Hidden Premise in the Causal Argument for Physicalism.” Analysis, 66, pp. 4452.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bishop, R. 2006b: “Downward Causation in Fluid Convection.” Synthese, 160, pp. 229–48.Google Scholar
Blitz, D. 1992: Emergent Evolution. New York: Kluwer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Boogerd, F., Bruggeman, F., Hofmeyr, S., and Westerhoff, H. 2007: Systems Biology: Philosophical Foundations. Amsterdam: Elsevier.Google Scholar
Boogerd, F., Bruggeman, F., Richardson, R., Stephan, A., and Westerhoff, H. 2005: “Emergence and its Place in Nature: A Case Study of Biochemical Networks.” Synthese, 145, pp. 131–64.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Borchert, D. (ed.) 2006: Encyclopedia of Philosophy. 2nd edition. New York: Gale Research.Google Scholar
Bowler, P. 2001: Reconciling Science and Religion: The Debate in Early Twentieth-Century Britain. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Broad, C. D. 1925: The Mind and its Place in Nature. London: Routledge Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
Brown, J. 1991: Laboratory of the Mind: Thought Experiments in the Natural Sciences. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Brown, J. 2004: “Why Thought Experiments Transcend Experience.” In Hitchcock (2004), pp. 23–43.Google Scholar
Brown, L., Pais, A., and Pippard, B. (eds.) 1995: Twentieth Century Physics. Second Edition. New York: CRC Press.Google Scholar
Brown, W., Murphy, N., and Malony, H. 1998: Whatever Happened to the Soul? Minneapolis, MN: Augsburg Fortress Press.Google Scholar
Camazine, S., Deneubourg, J., Franks, N., Sneyd, J., Theraulaz, G., and Bonabeau, E. 2001: Self-Organization in Biological Systems. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Campbell, D. 1974: “‘Downward Causation’ in Hierarchically Organized Biological Systems.” In Ayala and Dobzhansky (1974), pp. 179–86.Google Scholar
Cartwright, N. 1983: How the Laws of Physics Lie. Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cartwright, N. 1994: “Fundamentalism vs. the Patchwork of Laws.” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 103, pp. 279–92.Google Scholar
Cartwright, N. 1999: The Dappled World. New York: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cat, J. 1998: “The Physicists’ Debates on Unification in Physics at the End of the 20th Century.” Historical Studies in the Physical Sciences, 28, pp. 253–99.Google Scholar
Chalmers, D. 1997: The Conscious Mind. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Chalmers, D. 2006: “Strong and Weak Emergence.” In Clayton and Davies (2004, pp. 244–54.Google Scholar
Churchland, P.M. 1985: “Reduction, Qualia and the Direct Introspeciton of Brain States.” Journal of Philosophy, v.82, pp. 8–28.Google Scholar
Churchland, P.S. 1986: Neurophilosophy: Toward a Unified Science of the Mind-Brain. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Clapp, L. 2001: “Disjunctive Properties: Multiple Realizations.” Journal of Philosophy, 98, pp. 111–36.Google Scholar
Clayton, P. 1997: God and Contemporary Science. Grand Rapids, MI: Eerdmans.Google Scholar
Clayton, P. 2004: Mind and Emergence. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Clayton, P. (ed.) 2006: Oxford Handbook of Religion and Science. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Clayton, P., and Davies, P. (eds.) 2004: The Re-Emergence of Emergence. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Corning, P. 2002: “The Re-Emergence of ‘Emergence’: A Venerable Concept in Search of a Theory.” Complexity, 7, pp. 1830.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cornwell, J. (ed.) 1995: Nature’s Imagination. New York Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Corradini, A., and O’Connor, T. (eds.) 2011: Emergence in Science and Philosophy. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Couzin, I., and Krause, J. 2003: “Self-Organization and Collective Behavior in Vertebrates.” Advances in the Studies of Behavior, 33, pp. 175.Google Scholar
Crane, T. 2001: The Elements of Mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Craver, C. 2007: Explaining the Brain. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Craver, C., and Bechtel, B. 2007: “Top-Down Causation without Top-Down Causes.” Biology and Philosophy, 22, pp. 547–63.Google Scholar
Craver, C., and Darden, L. 2001: “Discovering Mechanisms in Neurobiology: The Case of Spatial Memory.” In P. Machamer, et al. (eds.), Theory and Method in Neuroscience. Pittsburgh, PA: University of Pittsburgh Press.Google Scholar
Crick, F. 1966: Of Mice and Molecules. Seattle, WA: University of Washington.Google Scholar
Crick, F. 1994: The Astonishing Hypothesis: The Scientific Search for the Soul. New York: Scribner.Google Scholar
Crook, S., and Gillett, C. 2001: “Why Physics Alone Cannot Define the ‘Physical’.” Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 31, pp. 333–60.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Crutchfield, J., Farmer, J., Packard, N., and Shaw, R. 1986: “Chaos.” Scientific American, 255, pp. 4657.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cummins, R. 1975: “Functional Analysis.” Journal of Philosophy, 72, pp. 741–65.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cummins, R. 1983: The Nature of Psychological Explanation. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Darden, L., and Maull, N. 1977: “Interfield Theories.” Philosophy of Science, 44, pp. 4364.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dawkins, R. 1982: The Extended Phenotype. San Francisco, CA: W. H. Freeman.Google Scholar
Dawkins, R. 1985: “Editorial.” In Dawkins and Ridley (1985).Google Scholar
Dawkins, R. 1987: The Blind Watchmaker. New York: Norton.Google Scholar
Dawkins, R., and Ridley, M. 1985: Oxford Surveys in Evolutionary Biology, vol. 2. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Delehanty, M. 2005: “Emergent Properties and the Context Objection to Reduction.” Biology and Philosophy, 20, pp. 715–34.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dennett, D. 1969: Content and Consciousness. London: Routledge Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
Dennett, D. 1978: Brainstorms. Montgomery, VT: Bradford Books.Google Scholar
Dennett, D. 1991: “Real Patterns.” Journal of Philosophy, 88, pp. 2751.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dennett, D. 1996: Darwin’s Dangerous Idea. New York: Simon and Schuster.Google Scholar
Dupré, J. 1993: The Disorder of Things: Metaphysical Foundations of the Disunity of Science. Boston, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Dupré, J. 2001: Human Nature and the Limits of Science. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dupré, J. 2008: The Constituents of Life. Assen: Van Gorcum.Google Scholar
Dupré, J. 2009: “It Is Not Possible to Reduce Biological Explanations to Explanations in Chemistry and/or Physics.” In Varela and Arp (2009), pp. 32–47.Google Scholar
Dyke, C. 1988: The Evolutionary Dynamics of Complex Systems: A Study in Biological Complexity. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Elkana, Y. 1974: The Discovery of the Conservation of Energy. London: Hutchinson.Google Scholar
Ellis, B. 2002: The Philosophy of Nature. Montreal: McGill University Press.Google Scholar
Endicott, R. 2006: “Multiple Realizability.” In Borchert (2006).Google Scholar
Esfeld, M., and Sachse, C. 2011: Conservative Reductionism. New York: Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fodor, J. 1968: Psychological Explanation. New York: Random House.Google Scholar
Fodor, J. 1974: “Special Sciences: Or, the Disunity of Science as a Working Hypothesis.” Synthese, 28, pp. 97115.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fodor, J. 1975: The Language of Thought. New York: Crowell.Google Scholar
Fodor, J. 1997: “Special Sciences: Still Autonomous after All These Years.” Philosophical Perspectives, 11.Google Scholar
Fodor, J. 1998: “Look! Review of E.O.Wilson’s Consilience.London Review of Books, v.20, No.21, 29 October, pp. 36.Google Scholar
Foster, J. 1991: The Immaterial Self: A Defence of the Cartesian Dualist Conception of the Mind. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Freeman, W. 1995: Societies of Brains. Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum.Google Scholar
Freeman, W. 1999: “Consciousness, Intentionality and Causality.” In Nunez and Freeman (1999), pp. 143–72.Google Scholar
Freeman, W. 2000a: How Brains Make Up Their Minds. New York: Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
Freeman, W. 2000b: Neurodynamics: An Exploration of Mescopic Brain Dynamics. London: Springer-Verlag.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Garfinkel, A. 1987: “The Slime Mold Dictyostelium as a Model of Self-Organization in Social Systems.” In Yates (1987), pp. 181–212.Google Scholar
Gilbert, S., and Sarkar, S. 2000: “Embracing Complexity: Organicism for the 21st Century.” Developmental Dynamics, 219, pp. 19.3.0.CO;2-A>CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gillett, C. 2002a: “The Varieties of Emergence: Their Purposes, Obligations and Importance.” Grazer Philosophische Studien, 65, pp. 89115.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gillett, C. 2002b: “The Dimensions of Realization: A Critique of the Standard View.” Analysis, 62, pp. 316–23.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gillett, C. 2003a: “Non-Reductive Realization and Non-Reductive Identity: What Physicalism Does Not Entail.” In S. Walter and H.-D. Heckmann (eds.) Physicalism and Mental Causation. Bowling Green, OH: Imprint Academic, pp. 31–58.Google Scholar
Gillett, C. 2003b: “Strong Emergence as a Defense of Non-Reductive Physicalism.” Special issue on emergence. Principia, 6, pp. 83114.Google Scholar
Gillett, C. 2003c: “The Metaphysics of Realization, Multiple Realizability and the Special Sciences.” Journal of Philosophy, 100, pp. 591–603.Google Scholar
Gillett, C. 2006a: “Samuel Alexander’s Emergentism: Or, Higher Causation for Physicalists.” Synthese, 153, pp. 261–96.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gillett, C. 2006b: “The Hidden Battles over Emergence.” In Clayton (1996).Google Scholar
Gillett, C. 2006c: “Special Sciences.” In Borchert (2006).Google Scholar
Gillett, C. 2006d: “The Metaphysics of Mechanisms and the Challenge of the New Reductionism.” In Schouten and de Joong (2006).Google Scholar
Gillett, C. 2007a: “Understanding the New Reductionism: The Metaphysics of Science and Compositional Reduction.” The Journal of Philosophy, 104, pp. 193216.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gillett, C. 2007b: “A Mechanist Manifesto for the Philosophy of Mind: A Third Way for Functionalists.” Journal of Philosophical Research, 32, pp. 2142.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gillett, C. 2007c: “Hyper-Extending the Mind? Setting Boundaries in the Special Sciences.” Philosophical Topics, 351, pp. 161–88.Google Scholar
Gillett, C. 2010: “Moving Beyond the Subset Model of Realization.” Synthese, 177, pp. 165–92.Google Scholar
Gillett, C. 2011a: “Multiply Realizing Scientific Properties and their Instances: A Response to Polger and Shapiro.” Philosophical Psychology, v.24, pp. 727–38.Google Scholar
Gillett, C. 2011b: “On the Implications of Scientific Composition and Completeness: Or, the Troubles, and Troubles, of Non-Reductive Physicalism.” In Corradini and O’Connor (2011).Google Scholar
Gillett, C. 2012: “Understanding the Sciences through the Fog of ‘Functionalism(s)’.” In Hunneman (2012), pp. 159–81.Google Scholar
Gillett, C. 2013: “Constitution, and Multiple Constitution, in the Sciences: Using the Neuron as a Guide.” Minds and Machines, v.23, pp. 309–37.Google Scholar
Gillett, C. 2016: “The Metaphysics of Nature, Science and the Rules of Engagement” in Aizawa and Gillett (2016).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gillett, C. Unpublished: “Making Sense of Levels in the Sciences.”Google Scholar
Gillett, C., and Loewer, B. (eds.) 2001: Physicalism and its Discontents. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gillett, C., and Rives, B. 2001: “Does the Argument from Realization Generalize? Responses to Kim.” Southern Journal of Philosophy, 39, pp. 7998.Google Scholar
Gillett, C., and Rives, B. 2005: “The Non-Existence of Determinables: Or, a World of Absolute Determinates as Default Hypothesis.” Nous, 39, pp. 483504.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Glennan, S. 1996: “Mechanisms and the Nature of Causation.” Erkenntnis, 44, pp. 4971.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goldbeter, A. 1997: Biochemical Oscillations and Cellular Rhythms: The Molecular Basis of Periodic and Chaotic Behavior. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Goldbeter, A., Gonze, D., Houart, G., Leloup, J., Halloy, J., and Dupont, G. 2001: “From Simple to Complex Oscillatory Behavior in Metabolic and Genetic Control Network.” Chaos, 11, pp. 247–60.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goldstein, J. 1999: “Emergence as a Construct: History and Issues.” Emergence, 1, pp. 4972.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goodwin, B. 2001: How the Leopard Changed its Spots: The Evolution of Complexity. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gregory, R., 1994: “DNA in the Mind’s Eye”. Nature, 368, pp. 359–60.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Groff, R., and Greco, J. 2012: Powers and Capacities in Philosophy: The New Aristotelianism. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Hall, N. 2004: “Two Concepts of Causation.” In J. Collins, N. Hall and L. Paul (eds.) Causation and Counterfactuals, pp. 22576. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Haraway, D. 1976: Crystals, Fabrics and Fields. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Harold, F. 2001: The Way of the Cell. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hasker, W. 1999: The Emergent Self. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Healey, R. 2013: “Physical Composition.” Studies in the History and Philosophy of Science Part B, 44, pp. 4862.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Heil, J. 1999: “Multiple Realizability.” American Philosophical Quarterly, 36, pp. 189208.Google Scholar
Heil, J. 2003: From an Ontological Point of View. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hempel, C. 1965: Aspects of Scientific Explanation and Other Essays in the Philosophy of Science. New York: Free Press.Google Scholar
Hempel, C., and Oppenheim, P. 1965: “On the Idea of Emergence.” In Hempel (1965), pp. 258–64.Google Scholar
Hendry, R. 1998: “Models and Approximations in Quantum Chemistry.” In Shanks, N. (ed.), Idealization in Contemporary Physics. Amsterdam: Rodopoi.Google Scholar
Hendry, R. 2006: “Is There Downward Causation in Chemistry?” In Baird et al. (eds.) Philosophy of Chemistry, pp. 173–89. Dordrecht: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hendry, R. 2010: “Emergence vs. Reduction in Chemistry.” In MacDonald and MacDonald (2010a), pp. 205–21.Google Scholar
Hendry, R., and Needham, P. 2007: “Le Poidevin on the Reduction of Chemistry.” British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 58, pp. 339–53.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hitchcock, C. (ed.) 2004: Contemporary Debates in the Philosophy of Science. Malden, MA: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Hohwy, J., and Kallestrup, J. (eds.) 2008: Being Reduced: New Essays on Reduction, Explanation and Causation. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Holland, J. 1999: Emergence: From Chaos to Order. New York: Basic Books.Google Scholar
Holldobler, B., and Wilson, E. 1990: The Ants. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Holldobler, B., and Wilson, E. 2009: The Superorganism: The Beauty, Elegance and Strangeness of Insect Societies. New York: NortonGoogle Scholar
Hooker, C. A. 1981: “Towards a General Theory of Reduction. Part I: Historical and Scientific Settings. Part II: Identity. Part III: Cross Categorial Reduction.” Dialogue, 20, pp. 3859, 201–36, 496529.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Horgan, J. 1997: The End of Science. New York: Broadway Books.Google Scholar
Horgan, T. 1993a: “From Supervenience to Superdupervenience: Meeting the Demands of a Material World.” Mind, 102, pp. 555–86.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Horgan, T. 1993b: “Nonreductive Materialism and the Explanatory Autonomy of Psychology.” In Wagner, S. and Warner, R. (eds.) Naturalism. South Bend: Notre Dame University Press.Google Scholar
Horst, S. 2007: Beyond Reduction: Philosophy of Mind and Post-Reductionist Philosophy of Science. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Howard, D. 2007: “Reduction and Emergence in the Physical Sciences: Some Lessons from the Particle Physics and Condensed Matter Debate.” In Murphy and Stoeger (2007).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Huemer, M. 2009: “When Is Parsimony a Virtue?Philosophical Quarterly, 59, pp. 216–36.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hull, D. 2002: “Varieities of Reductionism.” In Regenmortel and Hull (2002), pp. 161–72.Google Scholar
Humphreys, P. 1997: “How Properties Emerge”. Philosophy of Science, 64, pp. 1–17.Google Scholar
Humphreys, P. 2008a: “Synchronic and Diachronic Emergence.” Minds and Machines, 18, pp. 431–42.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Humphreys, P. 2008b: “Computational and Conceptual Emergence.” Philosophy of Science, 75, pp. 584–94.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hunneman, P. (ed.) 2012: Functions: Selection and Mechanisms. Dordrecht: Kluwer.Google Scholar
Imbert, C. 2007: “Why Diachronically Emergent Properties Must Also Be Salient.” In Gershenson, Aerts, and Edmonds (eds.), Worldviews, Science and Us, pp. 99–116. Hackensack, NJ: World Scientific Publishing Company.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Juarrero, A. 1999: Dynamics in Action: Intentional Behavior as a Complex System. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kandel, E. 2006: In Search of Memory. New York: Norton.Google Scholar
Kauffman, S. 1993: The Origins of Order: Self-Organization and Selection in Evolution. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kauffman, S. 1995: At Home in the Universe. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Kauffman, S., and Clayton, P. 2006: “On Emergence, Agency and Organization.” Biology and Philosophy, 21, pp. 501–21.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kellert, S. 1993: In the Wake of Chaos. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kim, J. 1972: “Phenomenal Properties, Psychological Laws, and Identity Theory.” Monist, 56, pp. 177–92.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kim, J. 1992a: “‘Downward Causation’ in Emergentism and Nonreductive Physicalism.” In Beckermann, Flohr, and Kim (1992).Google Scholar
Kim, J. 1992b: “Multiple Realization and the Metaphysics of Reduction.” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 52, pp. 126.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kim, J. 1993a: Supervenience and Mind. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kim, J. 1993b: “The Nonreductionist’s Troubles with Mental Causation.” In Kim (1993a).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kim, J. 1993c: “Dretske on How Reasons Explain Behaviour.” In Kim (1993a).Google Scholar
Kim, J. 1993d: “Postscripts on Supervenient Causation.” In Kim (1993a).Google Scholar
Kim, J. 1993e: “Mechanism, Purpose and Explanatory Exclusion.” In Kim (1993a).Google Scholar
Kim, J. 1997: “The Mind–Body Problem: Taking Stock after Forty Years.” Philosophical Perspectives, 11.Google Scholar
Kim, J. 1998: Mind in a Physical World. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kim, J. 1999: “Making Sense of Emergence.” Philosophical Studies, 95, pp. 344.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kim, J. 2003: “Blocking Causal Drainage and Other Maintenance Chores with Mental Causation.” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 67, pp. 151–76.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kim, J. 2006: “Being Realistic about Emergence.” In Clayton and Davies (2004), pp. 189–202Google Scholar
Kistler, M. 2010: “Mechanisms and Downward Causation.” Philosophical Psychology, 22, pp. 595–609.Google Scholar
Kitcher, P. 1984: “1953 and All That: A Tale of Two Sciences.” Philosophical Review, 93, pp. 335–73. Reprinted in his (2003). All references are to the reprint.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Kitcher, P. 2003: In Mendel’s Mirror. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kuhn, T. 1970: The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Ladyman, J., and Ross, D. 2007: Everything Must Go. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Laughlin, R. 2005: A Different Universe: Reinventing Physics from the Bottom Down. New York: Basic Books.Google Scholar
Laughlin, R., and Pines, D. 2000: “The Theory of Everything.” Proceedings of the National Academy of Science, 97, pp. 2831.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Laughlin, R., Pines, D., Schmalien, J., Stojkovic, B., and Wolynes, P. 2000: “The Middle Way,” Proceedings of the National Academy of Science, 97, pp. 32–7.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Levins, R., and Lewontin, R. 1987: The Dalectical Biologist. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Lewin, R. 1992: Complexity: Life at the Edge of Chaos. New York: Macmillan.Google Scholar
Lewis, David 1972: “Psychophysical and Theoretical Identifications.” Australasian Journal of Philosophy, v.50, pp. 249–58.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lewis, David 1983: “New Work for a Theory of Universals.” Australasian Journal of Philosophy, v.61, pp. 343–77.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Loewer, B. 1995: “An Argument for Strong Supervenience.” In Savellos and Yalcin (1995).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Loewer, B. 2001: “From Physics to Physicalism.” In Gillett and Loewer (eds.) (2001).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Loewer, B. 2008: “Why There Is Anything Except Physics.” In Hohwy and Kallestrup (2008).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lowe, J. 1996: The Subjects of Experience. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lowe, J. 2008: Personal Agency: The Metaphysics of Mind and Action. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lowe, J. 2009: “Dualism.” In McLaughlin, Beckermann, and Walter (2009), pp. 66–84.Google Scholar
Machamer, P., Darden, L., and Craver, C. 2000: “Thinking about Mechanisms.” Philosophy of Science, 67, pp. 125.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Maturana, H., and Varela, F. 1973: “Autopoiesis and Cognition.” In Cohen, R. S. and Wartofsky, M. W. (eds.), Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science, vol. 10, p. 42.Google Scholar
Mayr, E. 1988a: “The Limits of Reductionism.” Nature, 33.Google Scholar
Mayr, E. 1988b: Toward a New Philosophy of Biology. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Mayr, E. 2002: What Makes Biology Unique? Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
MacDonald, C., and MacDonald, G. (eds.) 2010a: Emergence in Mind. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
MacDonald, C., and MacDonald, G. 2010b: “Emergence and Downward Causation.” In MacDonald and MacDonald (2010a), pp. 139–68.Google Scholar
McGinn, C. 1993: The Problem of Consciousness: Essays Towards a Resolution. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
McLaughlin, B. 1992: “The Rise and Fall of British Emergentism.” In Beckermann, Flohr, and Kim (1992).Google Scholar
McLaughlin, B. 1995: “The Varieties of Supervenience.” In Savellos and Yalcin (1995).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McLaughlin, B., Beckermann, A., and Walter, S. 2009: The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Mind. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Mellor, H. 2008: “Micro-Composition”. Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplements, v.83, pp.81-106.Google Scholar
Melnyk, A. 1995: “Two Cheers for Reductionism; Or, The Dim Prospects for Nonreductive Materialism.” Philosophy of Science, 62, pp. 370–88.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Melnyk, A. 1997: “How to Keep the ‘Physical’ in Physicalism.” Journal of Philosophy, 94, pp. 622–37.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Melnyk, A. 2003: A Physicalist Manifesto. New York: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Merricks, T. 2001: Objects and Persons. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Midgley, M. 1995: “Reductive Megalomania.” In Cornwell (1995), pp. 133–47.Google Scholar
Mitchell, S. 2003: Biological Complexity and Integrative Pluralism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mitchell, S. 2009: Unsimple Truths: Science, Complexity and Policy. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mitchell, S. 2012: “Emergence: Logical, Functional and Dynamical.” Synthese, v.185, pp. 171–86.Google Scholar
Morowitz, H. 2002: The Emergence of Everything: How the World Became Complex. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mulligan, K., Simons, P., and Smith, B. 2006: “What’s Wrong with Contemporary Philosophy?Topoi, 25, pp. 63–7.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Murphy, N., and Brown, W. 2007: Did My Neurons Make Me Do It? New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Murphy, N., and Stoeger, W. 2007: Evolution and Emergence: Systems, Organisms, Persons. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nagel, E. 1952: “Wholes, Sums and Organic Unities.” Philosophical Studies, 2, pp. 1632.Google Scholar
Nagel, E. 1961: The Structure of Science. New York: Harcourt Brace.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Newman, D. 1996: “Emergence and Strange Attractors.” Philosophy of Science, 63, pp. 245–61.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Newton-Smith, W. 1981: The Rationality of Science. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nicolis, G., and Prigogine, I. 1989: Exploring Complexity. New York: Freeman.Google Scholar
Norton, J., 2004: “Why Thought Experiments Do Not Transcend Empiricism.” In Hitchcock (2004), pp. 44–66.Google Scholar
Nunez, R., and Freeman, W. (eds.) 1999: Reclaiming Cognition: The Primacy of Action, Intention and Emotion. Bowling Green, OH: Imprint Academic.Google Scholar
O’Connor, T. 1994: “Emergent Properties.” American Philosophical Quarterly, 31, pp. 91104.Google Scholar
O’Connor, T., and Churchill, J. 2010: “Is Non-Reductive Physicalism Viable within a Causal Powers Metaphysics?” In MacDonald and MacDonald (2010a), pp. 43–60.Google Scholar
O’Connor, T., and Jacobs, J. 2003: “Emergent Individuals.” Philosophical Quarterly, 53, pp. 540–55.Google Scholar
O’Connor, T., and Wong, H. 2003: “The Metaphysics of Emergence.” Noûs, 39, pp. 659–79.Google Scholar
O’Malley, M., and Dupré, J. 2005: “Fundamental Issues in Systems Biology.” BioEssays, 27, pp. 1270–6.Google ScholarPubMed
Papineau, D. 1993: Philosophical Naturalism. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.Google Scholar
Papineau, D. 1995: “Arguments for Supervenience and Physical Realization.” In Savellos and Yalcin (1995).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Papineau, D. 2001: “The Rise of Physicalism.” In Gillett and Loewer (2001).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Papineau, D. 2002: Thinking about Consciousness. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pattee, H. 1970: “The Problem of Biological Hierarchy.” In Waddington (1970), vol. 3, pp. 117–36.Google Scholar
Pattee, H. 1973a: “The Physical Basis and Origin of Hierarchical Control.” In Pattee (1973b).Google Scholar
Pattee, H. (ed.) 1973b: Hierarchy Theory. New York: George Braziller.Google Scholar
Peacocke, A. 1990: Theology for a Scientific Age. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.Google Scholar
Peacocke, A. 1995: “God’s Interaction with the World.” In Russell et al. (1995).Google Scholar
Peacocke, A. 1999: “The Sound of Sheer Silence: How Does God Communicate with Humanity?” In Russell et al. (1999).Google Scholar
Pereboom, D. 2011: Consciousness and the Prospects of Physicalism. New York: Oxford University PressCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pfeifer, J., and Sarkar, S. 2006: Philosophy of Science: An Encyclopedia. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Piccinini, G. 2004: “Functionalism, Computationalism, and Mental States.” Studies in the History and Philosophy of Science, 35, pp. 811–33.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Poland, J. 1994: Physicalism. Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Polanyi, M. 1968: “Life’s Irreducible Structure.” Science, 160, pp. 1308–12.Google ScholarPubMed
Polger, T. 2007: “Realization and the Metaphysics of Mind.” Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 85, pp. 233–59.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Prigogine, I. 1968: Introduction to Thermodynamics of Irreversible Processes. New York: Wiley.Google Scholar
Prigogine, I. 1997: End of Certainty. New York: The Free Press.Google Scholar
Prigogine, I., and Stengers, I. 1984: Order out of Chaos: Man’s New Dialogue with Nature. New York: Bantam Books.Google Scholar
Primas, H. 1983: Chemistry, Quantum Mechanics, and Reductionism. Berlin: Springer- Verlag.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Putnam, H. 1967: “Psychological Predicates.” In Capitan, W. and Merrill, D. (eds.), Art, Mind and Religion. Pittsburgh: Pittsburgh University Press. Reprinted as “The Nature of Mental States” in Putnam (1975b). (All references are to the reprint.)Google Scholar
Putnam, H. 1975a: “Philosophy and Our Mental Life.” In Putnam (1975b).Google Scholar
Putnam, H. 1975b: Mind, Language and Reality: Philosophical Papers, vol. 2. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Regenmortel, M., and Hull, D. 2002: Promises and Limits of Reductionism in the Biomedical Sciences. Chichester: John Wiley and Sons.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Richardson, R., and Stephan, A. 2007: “Mechanisms and Mechanical Explanation in Systems Biology.” In Boogerd et al. (2007), pp. 123–44.Google Scholar
Rosenberg, A. 2006: Darwinian Reductionism: Or, How to Stop Worrying and Love Molecular Biology. Chicago, IL: Chicago University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ross, D., and Spurrett, D. 2004: “What to Say to a Skeptical Metaphysician? A Defense Manual for Cognitive and Behavioral Scientists.” Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 27, pp. 603–27.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Rueger, A. 2000: “Robust Supervenience and Emergence.” Philosophy of Science, 67, pp. 466–91.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Russell, B. 1911: “Le Réalisme Analytique.” Bulletin de la Société Française de Philosophie, 11, pp. 5361.Google Scholar
Russell, J., Murphy, N., Meyering, T., and Arbib, A. (eds.) 1999: Neuroscience and the Person: Scientific Perspectives on Divine Action. Vatican City State: Vatican Observatory Publications.Google Scholar
Russell, J., Murphy, N., and Peacocke, A. (ed.) 1995: Chaos and Complexity: Scientific Perspectives on Divine Action. Vatican City State: Vatican Observatory Publications.Google Scholar
Salthe, S. 1985: Evolving Hierarchical Systems: Their Representation and Structure. New York: Columbia University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sarkar, S. 2005: Molecular Models of Life. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Savellos, E., and Yalcin, U. (eds.) 1995: Supervenience: New Essays. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Scerri, E. 1994: “Has Chemistry Been at Least Approximately Reduced to Quantum Mechanics?” In Hull, D., Forbes, M., and Burian, R. M. (eds.), PSA vol. 1, pp. 160–70.Google Scholar
Scerri, E. 1997: “Has the Periodic Table Been Successfully Axiomitized?Erkentnis, 47, pp. 229–43.Google Scholar
Scerri, E. 1998a: “Popper’s Naturalized Approach to the Reduction of Chemistry.” International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 12, pp. 3344.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Scerri, E. 1998b: “How Good is the Quantum Mechanical Explanation of the Periodic Table?Journal of Chemical Education, 75, pp. 1384–5.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Scerri, E. 2007: “Reduction and Emergence in Chemistry: Two Recent Approaches.” Philosophy of Science, 74, pp. 920–31.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schaffer, J. 2007: “From Nihilism to Monism.” Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 85, pp. 175–91.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schaffer, J. 2010: “Monism: The Priority of the Whole.” Philosophical Review, 119, pp. 3176.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schaffner, K. 1967: “Approaches to Reduction”. Philosophy of Science, v.34, pp. 137–47.Google Scholar
Schaffner, K. 1993: Discovery and Explanation in Biology and Medicine. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Schaffner, K. 2002: “Reductionism, Complexity and Molecular Medicine: Genetic Chips and the ‘Globalization’ of the Genome.” In Regenmortel and Hull (2002), pp. 323–51.Google Scholar
Schaffner, K. 2006: “Reduction: The Cheshire Cat Problem and a Return to Roots.” Synthese, 151, pp. 377402.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schouten, M., and de Joong, H. 2006: The Matter of Mind: Philosophical Essays on Psychology, Neuroscience and Reduction. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Scott, A. 2007: The Non-Linear Universe: Chaos, Emergence, Life. New York: Springer.Google Scholar
Seeley, T. 1989: “Social Foraging in Honey Bees: How Nectar Foragers Assess Their Colony’s Nutritional Status.” Behavioral Ecology and Sociobiology, 24, pp. 181–99.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Seeley, T. 1995: The Wisdom of the Hive: The Social Physiology of Honey Bee Colonies. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sellars, W. 1963: “Philosophy and the Scientific Image of Man.” In Colodny, R. (ed.), pp. 3578, Science, Perception, and Reality. New York: Humanities Press/Ridgeview.Google Scholar
Shapiro, L. 2000: “Multiple Realizations”. Journal of Philosophy, 97, pp. 635–54.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shapiro, L. 2004: The Mind Incarnate. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Shapiro, L. 2010: “Lessons from Causal Exclusion.” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 88, pp. 594–604.Google Scholar
Shapiro, L. 2011: “Mental Manipulations and the Problem of Causal Exclusion.” Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 90, pp. 118.Google Scholar
Shoemaker, S. 1980: “Causality and Properties.” In Van Inwagen (1980).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shoemaker, S. 2001: “Realization and Mental Causation.” In Gillett and Loewer (2001).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shoemaker, S. 2003a: “Realization, Micro-Realization and Coincidence.” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 67, pp. 1–23.Google Scholar
Shoemaker, S. 2003b: “Kim on Emergence.” Philosophical Studies, 108, pp. 5363.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shoemaker, S. 2007: Physical Realization. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Siderits, M. 2007: Buddhism as Philosophy: An Introduction. Cambridge: Hackett.Google Scholar
Silberstein, M., and McGeever, J. 1999: “The Search for Ontological Emergence.” The Philosophical Quarterly, 49, pp. 183200.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Simon, H. 1969: The Sciences of the Artificial. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Sklar, L. 1967: “Types of Inter-Theoretic Reduction.” The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 18, pp. 109–24.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sklar, L. 1995: Physics and Chance: Philosophical Issues in the Foundations of Statistical Mechanics. New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Sorenson, A., Busch, T., and Vinson, S. 1985: “Control of Food Influx by Temporal Subcastes in the Fire Ant, Solenopsis invicta.” Behavioral Ecology and Sociobiology, 17, pp. 191–8.Google Scholar
Sorger, P. 2005: “A Reductionist’s Systems Biology.” Current Opinion in Cell Biology, 17, pp. 911.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Sperry, R. 1986: “Macro-Determinism vs. Microdeterminism.” Philosophy of Science, 53, pp. 265–70.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sperry, R. 1992: “Turnabout on Consciousness: A Mentalist View.” Journal of Mind and Behaviour, 13, pp. 259–80.Google Scholar
Spurrett, D. 1999: The Completeness of Physics. Phd thesis: University of Natal.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stephan, A. 1999: “Varieties of Emergentism.” Evolution and Cognition, 5, pp. 4959.Google Scholar
Stump, E. 2012: “Emergence, Causal Powers, and Aristotelianism in Metaphysics.” In Groff and Greco (2012).Google Scholar
Teller, P. 1992: “A Contemporary Look at Emergence.” In Beckermann et al. (1992), pp. 139–53.Google Scholar
Van Fraassen, B. 1980: The Scientific Image. Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Van Gulick, R. 1993: “Who’s in Charge Here? And Who’s Doing All the Work?” In Heil and Mele (eds.) Mental Causation. New York: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Van Gulick, R. 2001: “Reduction, Emergence and Other Options on the Mind/Body Problem.” Journal of Consciousness Studies, 8, pp. 134.Google Scholar
Van Inwagen, P. (ed.) 1980: Time and Cause. Dordrecht: Reidel.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Van Inwagen, P. 1990: Material Beings. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Waddington, C. 1970: Towards a Theoretical Biology. 4 vols. Chicago, IL: Aldine Publishing.Google Scholar
Weinberg, S. 1992: Dreams of a Final Theory. New York: Random House.Google Scholar
Weinberg, S. 2001: Facing Up: Science and its Cultural Adversaries. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Weiner, N. 1948: Cybernetics or Control and Communication in the Animal and the Machine. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Whitehead, A. N. 1925: Science and the Modern World. London: Free Press.Google Scholar
Wilkes, K. 1988: Real People: Personal Identity without Thought Experiments. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Williams, G. C. 1985: “A Defense of Reductionism in Evolutionary Biology.” In Dawkins and Ridley (1985), pp. 1–27.Google Scholar
Wilson, E. 1998: Consilience: The Unity of Knowledge. New York: Knopf.Google Scholar
Wilson, E., and Holldobler, B. 1988: “Dense Heterarchies and Mass Communication as the Basis of Organization in Ant Colonies.” Trends in Ecology and Evolution, 3, pp. 6584.Google ScholarPubMed
Wilson, J. 1999: “How Superduper Does a Physicalist Supervenience Need to Be?Philosophical Quarterly, 49, pp. 3352.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wilson, J. 2005: “Supervenience-Based Formulations of Physicalism.” Nous, 29, pp. 426–59.Google Scholar
Wilson, J. 2010: “Non-Reductive Physicalism and Degrees of Freedom.” British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 61, pp. 279311.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wilson, J. 2014: “No Work for a Theory of Grounding.” Inquiry, 57, pp. 145.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wilson, J. Forthcoming: “Metaphysical Emergence: Weak and Strong.” In T. Bigaj and C. Wuthrich (eds.) Metaphysics in Contemporary Physics. Poznan Studies in the Philosophy of the Sciences and the Humanities.Google Scholar
Wimsatt, W. 1976: “Reductionism, Levels of Organization and the Mind–Body Problem.” In Conciousness and the Brain, ed. by Globus, G., Maxwell, G., and Savodnik, I.. New York: Plenum Press.Google Scholar
Wimsatt, W. 1997: “Aggregativity: Reductive Heuristics for Finding Emergence.” Philosophy of Science, 64, pp. S372S384.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wimsatt, W. 2000: “Emergence as Nonaggregativity and the Biases of Reductionisms.” Foundations of Science, 5, pp. 269–97.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wimsatt, W. 2007: Re-Engineering Philosophy for Limited Beings. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Wimsatt, W., and Sarkar, S. 2006: “Reductionism.” In Pfeifer and Sarkar (2006), vol. 2, pp. 696–703.Google Scholar
Woolley, R. 1985 “The Molecular Structure Conundrum”. Journal of Chemical Education, v.62.Google Scholar
Woolley, R and Sutcliffe, B. 1977: “Molecular Structure and the Born-Oppenheimer Approximation”. Chemical Physics Letters, v.45.Google Scholar
Yates, F. (ed.) 1987: Self-Organizing Systems: The Emergence of Order. New York: Plenum Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

  • Bibliography
  • Carl Gillett, Northern Illinois University
  • Book: Reduction and Emergence in Science and Philosophy
  • Online publication: 05 September 2016
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9781139871716.014
Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

  • Bibliography
  • Carl Gillett, Northern Illinois University
  • Book: Reduction and Emergence in Science and Philosophy
  • Online publication: 05 September 2016
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9781139871716.014
Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

  • Bibliography
  • Carl Gillett, Northern Illinois University
  • Book: Reduction and Emergence in Science and Philosophy
  • Online publication: 05 September 2016
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9781139871716.014
Available formats
×