We use cookies to distinguish you from other users and to provide you with a better experience on our websites. Close this message to accept cookies or find out how to manage your cookie settings.
To save content items to your account,
please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies.
If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account.
Find out more about saving content to .
To save content items to your Kindle, first ensure no-reply@cambridge.org
is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings
on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part
of your Kindle email address below.
Find out more about saving to your Kindle.
Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations.
‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi.
‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.
Poverty has been a factor in history almost since time immemorial. It is only since the Industrial Revolution in the late eighteenth century that the idea of mass material well-being has become possible. Political Economy began around that time in Britain, France and Italy. In England at the time, the relief of the poor was supervised by the Church in every parish. Those who could not work – the elderly, the disabled, women with children – were called paupers. They received relief from rates collected by the Church from the local better-off households. The category ‘poor’ was applied to daily workers, mainly working on the land, who received a wage which traditionally was enough to feed the worker, his wife and their children.
It was when inflation of wheat (corn) prices occurred in the decade following the French Revolution that rates were collected for the working poor as well. At this stage Thomas Malthus conceived the idea that population grew at a geometric rate but food output only at arithmetic rate, hence there was a danger of overpopulation. His real purpose was to say that the working poor should not receive payments in addition to their wage since they would only breed more children and the money (paid in rates by the rich) would be wasted. David Ricardo, the most influential economist of his time and for centuries later, confirmed Malthus’s view.
Political Economy became hostile to any idea of relieving poverty as inimical to the laws of the market. It took a century of democratic struggle to broaden the franchise as well as the First World War to bring about a universal franchise. It was then that the idea of income redistribution from the rich to the poor was introduced in Political Economy by Arthur Cecil Pigou (I have discussed this in my Poverty of Political Economy, Harper and Collins, 2023).
It took another world war to establish the idea that relief of poverty was the task of the government. This was especially so because democracy had spread across the world. International agencies were set up and began to make comparisons between nations. We became conscious of advanced versus emerging economies.
The unorthodox estimation procedure, which Phillips (1958) adopted in his original paper, is examined using the Haar wavelet filter. The application of the Haar wavelet transform to Phillips’ original data shows that Phillips’ six pairs of mean coordinates display a striking similarity with the Haar scaling coefficients that represent averages with a period greater than 16 years. This is consistent with Desai’s (1975) intuition on the interpretation of the Phillips Curve. We show that the choice of sorting observations by ascending values of the unemployment rate is crucial for reaching the goal of estimating the eye-catching nonlinear hyperbolic shape of the wage–unemployment relationship that would be otherwise linear. Interestingly, the Haar filter can account not only for the facts characterizing the Phillips’ relationship up to the early 1960s but also for two important facts mostly debated among policymakers: the downward shift of the Phillips Curve and its flattening over time.
The Cambridge Economic History of India, published in two volumes, aims at tracing the changes in the economy of India from the thirteenth to the middle of the present century and beyond. The second volume covers the period 1757–1970, from the establishment of British rule to its termination, with epilogues on the post-Independence period. Part I opens with a broad description of the economy in the middle of the eighteenth century, then describes general economic trends in four main regions up to the middle of the nineteenth century, and includes a discussion of changes in the agrarian structure up to the end of 1947. Part II takes up various themes for the economy as a whole, while Part III deals with post-Independence developments in India and Pakistan. The Cambridge Economic History of India will be widely accepted as the standard work of reference on the subject, and the volumes will be of relevance to fields other than economic history, being the first major collaborative work of its kind to explore the shift of an advanced Asian civilization from pre-colonial times to independence.
Hayek is recognized as the philosopher/economist who championed liberty and opposed socialism. Marx, especially after the experience of bolshevism, is seen as the high priest, if not the god, of socialism and the enemy of liberty. Hayek is thus anti-Marx as he is also anti-Keynes. Yet there are few direct references to Marx in Hayek's writings; and Marxists, for most of the period when Hayek was writing and beyond, have ignored him. (Gamble 1996 is a notable exception.) Democratic socialists or social democrats engaged in the debates about socialist calculation with Hayek much more in the 1930s (Hayek 1935b; Durbin 1985). By the time Hayek wrote his final book, The Fatal Conceit: The Errors of Socialism (1988), the Soviet Union was close to collapse and socialism as a doctrine had become beleaguered. Hayek was celebrated as the philosopher who inspired those who subverted the Soviet empire in Eastern Europe. But it could be argued that by then Marx had little to do with Eastern Europe or the Soviet Union (Desai 2002).
The theorising of the natural rate of unemployment (NRU) almost simultaneously by Phelps (1967) and Friedman (1968) was a significant step in the halt and ultimately reversal of the Keynes–neoclassical synthesis (neoKeynesian) in the field of macroeconomic theory as well as policy. Both Phelps and Friedman were of course reacting to the Phillips curve which in their view did not have sufficient grounding in neoclassical economics. The central issue was the seeming violation of the homogeneity postulate, since the Phillips curve purported to show a short-run, causal relationship between a nominal variable and a real variable. The neo Keynesians were uncomfortable with this because while they liked the macroeconomic simplicity of the Phillips curve, they also believed in the homogeneity postulate. The empirical/econometric connection between these ideas and the Phillips curve was made in two stages. In the first stage, Lucas and Rapping in two papers reversed the causal ordering between the rate of change of money wages (Δw) and the rate of unemployment (U) from that posited by Phillips, or rather more correctly by Lipsey (1960), (Lucas and Rapping, 1969, 1970; for the argument that Phillips did not have the same notion of causation that Lipsey and others have attributed to him, see Desai 1975, 1984). At this stage, price expectations were taken to be adaptive. In the second stage, Lucas engineered the creative union between rational expectations (RE) and the natural rate hypothesis (NRH), (Lucas, 1973).
The idea of the core of an economy and the convergence of core allocations to the competitive equilibrium are well established in the economic literature. It has been assumed by most authors on this topic that it was Edgeworth who in his Mathematics Psychics first stated and proved the major result concerning the core. [Debreu and Scarf (1963), Arrow and Hahn (1971)]. The purpose of this paper is to draw attention to an essay by Turgot where the idea of the core is clearly stated and an argument about the convergence of the core to the competitive equilibrium as the number of consumers increases is first presented. Edgeworth’s Mathematical Psychics came out in 1881, Turgor’s essay was written some time in the 1760’s, definitely by 1770, but did not appear until Du Pont published his Oeuvres in 1808. Either way, if we can persuasively argue Turgot's claim then the discovery of this result is pushed back by more than a hundred years.