To save content items to your account,
please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies.
If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account.
Find out more about saving content to .
To save content items to your Kindle, first ensure no-reply@cambridge.org
is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings
on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part
of your Kindle email address below.
Find out more about saving to your Kindle.
Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations.
‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi.
‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.
This chapter examines the transformative effects of generative AI (GenAI) on competition law, exploring how GenAI challenges traditional business models and antitrust regulations. The evolving digital economy, characterised by advances in deep learning and foundation models, presents unique regulatory challenges due to market power concentration and data control. This chapter analyses the approaches adopted by the European Union, United States, and United Kingdom to regulate the GenAI ecosystem, including recent legislation such as the EU Digital Markets Act, the AI Act, and the US Executive Order on AI. It also considers foundational models’ reliance on key resources, such as data, computing power, and human expertise, which shape competitive dynamics across the AI market. Challenges at different levels—including infrastructure, data, and applications—are investigated, with a focus on their implications for fair competition and market access. The chapter concludes by offering insights into the balance needed between fostering innovation and mitigating the risks of monopolisation, ensuring that GenAI contributes to a competitive and inclusive market environment.
The experimental investigation focuses on the effects of a short splitter plate on the flow physics of a circular cylinder in proximity to a wall by particle image velocimetry. The Reynolds number is Re = 3900, and the near-wall cylinder is immersed in turbulent boundary layer flow. Three gap ratios (i.e. $G/D$ = 0.25, 0.5 and 1) are considered, and the splitter plate length is $L/D=0$, 0.25, 0.5, 0.75 and 1. For $G/D$ = 0.5 and 1, as $L/D$ increases from 0 to 1, the splitter plate facilitates the cylinder shear layers to elongate downstream, and the vortex formation length is increased, which leads to the increase of the range of the recirculation region. For $G/D$ = 0.25, the wall suppression on the wake vortex formation is enhanced, and the variations of the vortex formation length and the range of the recirculation region with $L/D$ are small. The Strouhal number St presents a decrease with increasing $L/D$ for the three gap ratios. The effects of $L/D$ on the vortex evolution are revealed. For $G/D$ = 0.5 and 1, as $L/D$ increases, the induction of the lower wake vortex on the wall secondary vortex becomes weaker due to the reduction in strength of the wake vortex and the increase of the vortex formation length. Additionally, the wake fluctuation intensity is decreased with the increase of $L/D$ due to the splitter plate suppression. For $G/D$ = 0.25, theL/D influences on evolution of the wake vortices and wall secondary vortex are small, which result in weaker variation of the wake fluctuation intensity with $L/D$.
The Stoics have sometimes been credited with concern for appropriately moral motivation, based on their distinction between those actions they classify as appropriate (kathēkonta) and those they characterize, in addition, as done on the basis of virtue (katorthōmata). This chapter argues that the Kantian and Stoic views closely resemble one another in this respect: just as Kant’s motive of duty requires a singular interest in the rightness of dutiful action, so the Stoics suppose that virtue and actions that originate in virtue are the only objects of fully rational desire. Both theories recognize, as well, that many of our cognitions are not transparent to ourselves, so that we are often unaware of our own motives. This recognition speaks to the depth and complexity of Stoic intellectualist psychology and underlies Kant’s claim that the effort to understand our own moral condition is a “wide” duty of virtue.
Edited by
Marietta Auer, Max Planck Institute for Legal History and Legal Theory,Paul B. Miller, University of Notre Dame, Indiana,Henry E. Smith, Harvard Law School, Massachusetts,James Toomey, University of Iowa
The final chapter of the book reflects on its lessons, concluding that the responsiveness of NJMs to the dynamics lying behind grievances – understood as fields of struggle – is key to delivering remedy. This is true whether the relevant NJM is central to that struggle, or whether (as is more often the case) it plays a more peripheral or supportive role within broader processes of decentered regulation. Transnational NJMs may lack coercive power, but they span jurisdictions that state bodies have difficulty regulating. In principle, they have greater capacity to design new approaches as problems arise, benefiting from independence, shorter institutional histories and more capacity to experiment than state bodies, which can experience stronger institutional inertia and political constraints. To strengthen their capacity to build and sustain influence, NJMs should be designed to be nimble, with a range of functions and structures and resourced with staff capable of reading and navigating the deeply contested fields of business and human rights.
Adam Smith ridicules the Stoics for neglecting the objects of virtuous choice. They think of life, he says, as a kind of game, the point of which is not winning but playing well, playing fairly and playing skillfully. The Stoics thus misrepresent what is at stake in our lives. This chapter discusses the difference between Kantian and Stoic ethics by focusing on questions raised by Smith’s analogy: Should the Stoics be troubled by his critique? Can the same criticism be leveled against Kantian ethics? How does the Kantian category of conditional goodness differ from the Stoic category of moral indifferents? And is Kant’s anti-eudaimonism – his insistence that virtue does not coincide with happiness – as significant a departure from Stoicism as he would have us believe?
This chapter tackles the question: What opportunities and liabilities did living, breathing veterans of 1930s Cuban antifascism present to Cuban revolutionary leaders beginning in 1959? It explores the convoluted, often transnational trajectories of individual antifascist Cubans from the 1930s forward. In so doing, it intervenes into the historiographies of both transnational antifascism and the Cuban Revolution, the former which has until recently mostly ignored Cuba and the latter which has mostly ignored antifascism. Individual human stories that demonstrate the multifaceted interactions of 1930s Cuban antifascism with the Cuban Revolution counter oversimplification, omission, politicization, and romanticization. The chapter concludes that historical memory of 1930s Cuban antifascism existed in post-1959 Cuba only to the extent to which it stood in explicit support of the Cuban Revolution, at least through the end of the twentieth century, and that it served ideological and pragmatic purposes
When one contemplates the remarkable expansion in research interest in African phenomena among social scientists on both sides of the Atlantic, the need for an up-to-date inventory of completed, continuing and projected research becomes increasingly apparent. Field research is costly; knowledge should be cumulative; reproduction ought to be systematic; and effective rapport with the human actors concerned should be scrupulously preserved. These and many other considerations dictate closer liaison among scholars everywhere in the organization and planning of future research on African subjects.
The purpose of this report is to provide a brief analytical survey of the character of research on Africa recently completed, or currently being pursued, by social scientists associated with European centers. There is, of course, a certain arbitrariness in focusing upon the state of research in European centers only, particularly in view of the very close organizational links between metropolitan institutions and associated research centers and institutes in the African territories. Moreover, as an increasingly greater proportion of the total research activity is being carried on by agencies established in Africa, a survey of the European centers provides us with only a partial picture of the overall dimensions of research sponsored and supported by the European countries concerned. In this report, however, space considerations unfortunately dictate this narrower focus upon the European side only.
We report on the experimental and theoretical characterisation of shallow water wave guiding along a curved wave guide. A curved beam of fixed height and width positioned at the bottom of a wave tank generates an effective step-like perturbation which can guide surface water waves. We construct a linear wave theory for this wave propagation and characterise the parameter region where wave guiding can develop, as well as the possible guided modes, their profile and propagation constant. The theoretical analysis is supported by experimental surface wave data. A good agreement is found between experimental data and theoretical predictions, which gives insight into the possible harnessing of wave-guiding phenomena for energy harvesting.
Edited by
Marietta Auer, Max Planck Institute for Legal History and Legal Theory,Paul B. Miller, University of Notre Dame, Indiana,Henry E. Smith, Harvard Law School, Massachusetts,James Toomey, University of Iowa
Reinach’s thesis that there is a legal a priori is as bold as it is interesting. It is bold because it excludes all sources of positive law and claims that certain legal propositions can be known independent of all actual legal systems. The thesis is especially interesting as it does not rely on natural law but rather on immediate insight into a priori legal propositions. Given the great variety of possible a priori propositions, the chapter focuses on necessary, essential, and nonpositive ones. All of them do not reveal a legal a priori, which casts the existence of a legal a priori into doubt. However, the phenomenon of self-evident propositions remains important. One just needs to analyse them differently with the help of nonpositive legal reasons.