Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-76fb5796d-25wd4 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-28T04:00:34.326Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Coercion vs. indeterminacy in opaque verbs

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  30 March 2017

Reinhard Kähle
Affiliation:
Universidade de Coimbra, Portugal
Get access

Summary

Introduction. This paper is about the semantic analysis of opaque verbs such as seek and owe, which allow for unspecific readings of their indefinite objects. One may be looking for a good car without there being any car that one is looking for; or, one may be looking for a good car in that a specific car exists that one is looking for. It thus appears that there are two interpretations of these verbs—a specific and an unspecific one—and one may wonder how they are related. The present paper is a contribution to this question.

History

Paris. The time of the holy inquisition. Opaque verbs differ in their semantic behaviour from ordinary verbs. This phenomenon was already known to the medieval logician Buridanus:

I posit the case that for a good service you performed forme, I promised you a good horse. [] And since I owe you this, until I have paid that concerning the payment of which I have obligated myself [], you could rightly take action against me to bring about payment to you of a horse, which you could not do if I did not owe you. [] But the opposite is argued in a difficult way.

[Buridanus (1966 [1350]: 137)]

The followingmodern version of the opposite argument is less verbose than the original:

Let us then have our horse-coper arguing again. “If I owe you a horse, then I owe you something. And if I owe you something, then there is something I owe you. And this can only be a thoroughbred of mine: you aren't going to say that in virtue of what I said there's something else I owe you. Very well, then: by your claim, there's one of my thoroughbreds I owe you. Please tell me which one it is.”

[Geach (1965: 430)]

The two arguments are based on two different ways of reading the sentence under debate (1) — an obvious, unspecific interpretation and a somewhat remote, specific one.

Type
Chapter
Information
Intensionality , pp. 217 - 265
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2005

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

[1] M., Aloni, Quantification under conceptual covers, Dissertation, University of Amsterdam, 2001.
[2] N., Asher, A typology for attitude verbs and their anaphoric properties, Linguistics and Philosophy, vol. 10 (1987), pp. 125–198.Google Scholar
[3] M., Bennett, A variation and extension of a montague fragment of English, Montague grammar (B., Partee, editor), Academic Press, New York, 1976, pp. 119–163.
[4] R., Blutner, Lexical semantics and pragmatics, Semantics (F., Hamm and T. E., Zimmermann, editors), Buske, Hamburg, 2002, pp. 27–58.
[5] J., Buridanus, Sophisms on meaning and truth, Translated by T. K., Scott, Appliton-Century- Crofts, New York, 1966, (= Sophismata, 1350).
[6] A., Copestake and T., Briscoe, Semi-productive polysemy and sense extension, Journal of Semantics, vol. 12 (1995), pp. 15–67.Google Scholar
[7] M. J., Cresswell, Logics and languages, Methuen, London, 1973.
[8] M. J., Cresswell and A., von Stechow, De re belief generalized, Linguistics and Philosophy, vol. 5 (1982), pp. 503–535.Google Scholar
[9] H., de Swart, Tense, aspect and coercion in a cross-linguistic perspectives, Proceedings of the Berkeley formal grammar conference workshops (M. Butt and T. H. King, editors), On-line publication 2000. cslipublications.stanford.edu/LFG/5/bfg00/bfg00-toc.html.
[10] G., Forbes, Objectual attitudes, Linguistics and Philosophy, vol. 23 (2000), pp. 141–183.
[11] G., Frege, Die Grundlagen der Arithmetik, Koebner, Breslau, 1884, [The Foundations of Arithmetic. Translated by J. L., Austin. Oxford 1950].
[12] P., Geach, A medieval discussion of intentionality, Logic, methodology and philosophy of science (Y., Bar-Hillel, editor), North Holland, Amsterdam, 1965, pp. 425–433.
[13] I., Heim, The semantics of definite and indefinite noun phrases, Dissertation, UMass at Amherst, 1982.
[14] I., Heim, Presupposition projection and the semantics of attitude verbs, Journal of Semantics, vol. 9 (1992), pp. 183–221.Google Scholar
[15] I., Heim and A., Kratzer, Semantics in generative grammar, Oxford University Press, Oxford, 1998.
[16] H., Hendriks, Studied flexibility, Dissertation, University of Amsterdam, 1993.
[17] T. M. V., Janssen, Compositionality, Handbook of logic and language (J., van Benthem and A., ter Meulen, editors), (With an appendix by B. H., Partee), Elsevier, Amsterdam, 1997, pp. 417–473.
[18] H., Kamp, A theory of truth and semantic representation, Formal methods in the study of language, Part 1 (J. A. G., Groenendijk et al., editors),Mathematical Centre Tracts, Amsterdam, 1981, pp. 277–322.
[19] D., Kaplan, Quantifying in, Words and objections: Essays on the work of W. V. Quine (D., Davidson and J., Hintikka, editors), Reidel, Dordrecht, 1969, pp. 206–242.
[20] D., Kaplan, How to Russell a Frege-Church, Journal of Philosophy, vol. 72 (1975), pp. 716– 729.Google Scholar
[21] D., Kaplan, Demonstratives. an essay on the semantics, logic, metaphysics and epistemology of demonstratives and other indexicals, Themes from Kaplan (J., Almog, J., Perry, and H., Wettstein, editors), Oxford University Press, Oxford, 1989, pp. 481–563.
[22] M., Krifka, For a structured meaning account of questions and answers, Audiatur Vox Sapientiae (C., Fèry andW. Sternefeld, editors), Akademic-Verlag, Berlin, 2001, pp. 287–319.
[23] R., Larson, M., den Dikken, and P., Ludlow, Intensional transitive verbs and abstract clausal complementation, Manuscript, SUNY at Stony Brook, 1999.
[24] D., Lewis, Attitudes de dicto and de se, The Philosophical Review, vol. 88 (1979), pp. 513– 543.
[25] D., Lewis, What puzzling Pierre does not believe, Australasian Journal of Philosophy, vol. 59 (1981), pp. 283–289.Google Scholar
[26] F., Moltmann, Intensional verbs and quantifiers, Natural Language Semantics, (1997), pp. 1–52.Google Scholar
[27] R., Montague, On the nature of certain philosophical entities, Monist, vol. 53 (1969), pp. 159–195.Google Scholar
[28] R., Montague, English as a formal language, Linguaggi nella societ`a e nella tecnica (B., Visentini, editor), Edizioni di Communit`a,Milan, 1970a, pp. 189–223.Google Scholar
[29] R., Montague, Universal grammar, Theoria, vol. 36 (1970b), pp. 373–398.
[30] R., Montague, The proper treatment of quantification in ordinary English, Approaches to natural language (J., Hintikka et al., editors), Reidel, Dordrecht, 1973, pp. 221–242.
[31] B., Partee, Noun phrase interpretation and type shifting principles, Studies in discourse representation theory and the theory of generalized quantifiers (J., Groenendijk et al., editors), Foris, Dordrecht, 1987, pp. 115–143.
[32] B., Partee, Montague grammar, Handbook of logic and language (J., van Benthem and A., ter Meulen, editors), [With H. Hendriks], Elsevier, Amsterdam, 1997, pp. 5–91.
[33] B., Partee and M., Rooth, Generalized conjunction and type ambiguity, Meaning, use, and interpretation of language (R., Bäuerle et al., editors), de Grugter, Berlin, 1983, pp. 361–383.
[34] J., Pustejovsky, Type coercion and lexical selection, Semantics and the lexicon (J., Pustejovsky, editor), Kluwer, Dordrecht, 1993, pp. 73–94.
[35] W. V. O., Quine, Quantifiers and propositional attitudes, Journal of Philosophy, vol. 53 (1956), pp. 177–187.Google Scholar
[36] W. V. O., Quine, Word and object, MIT Press, Cambridge,Mass., 1960.
[37] M., Rooth and B., Partee, Conjunction, type ambiguity, and wide scope “or”, Proceedings of the 1st west coast conference on formal linguistics (Stanford) (D. Flickinger et al., editors), 1982, pp. 353–362.Google Scholar
[38] T. E., Zimmermann, On the proper treatment of opacity in certain verbs, Natural Language Semantics, vol. 1 (1993), pp. 149–179.Google Scholar
[39] T. E., Zimmermann, Free choice disjunction and epistemic possibility, Natural Language Semantics, vol. 8 (2000), pp. 255–290.Google Scholar
[40] T. E., Zimmermann, Unspecificity and intensionality, Audiatur Vox Sapientiae (C., Fèry and W., Sternefeld, editors), Akademic-Verlag, Berlin, 2001, pp. 514–533.

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×