Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-76fb5796d-vfjqv Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-28T16:06:55.240Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Intensionality in philosophy andmetamathematics

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  30 March 2017

Reinhard Kähle
Affiliation:
Universidade de Coimbra, Portugal
Get access

Summary

Abstract. The relation between intensionality as understood in philosophy and in metamathematics (in particular in early writings of S. Feferman) is explored in this paper. It investigates whether the latter can be interpreted as an instance of the former and presents metamathematical examples of “serious intensionality”.

Truth and reference (i.e., extensions) on the one side and meaning (i.e., intensions) on the other side are closely related: for example, principles like every true sentence is meaningful and expressions with the same meaning refer to the same things (if they refer) seem to be correct from an intuitive point of view. Of course, this does not mean that, e.g., truth or falsity are the meanings of (declarative) sentences. Nonetheless, were it not because of contexts taken from ordinary language — like those containing modalities and propositional attitudes — expressions like “meaning” could perhaps be explained by employing terminology taken solely from referential semantics. Thus, it has been claimed that for scientific purposes one may well get on with purely extensional languages.1 In fact, this seems to be “obviously” true for the mathematical discourse.

It is mainly due to the work of S. Feferman that the topic of intensionality has nevertheless gained some relevance, perhaps even popularity, in the field of metamathematics (cf. primarily [12]). But what is the relation between “intensionality” as understood in philosophy and as understood in metamathematics? Are these two concepts actually the same? If not, is it at least possible to make them fruitful for each other, e.g., by construing one of them as a special case of the other? This paper addresses these questions both from a conceptual perspective and by presenting relevant metamathematical results.

Intensionality in philosophy: an overview.

Intensionality: basic phrases. When dealing with intensionality, a natural starting point is G. Frege's distinction (see his seminal [16]) between “Bedeutung” (i.e., reference) and “Sinn” (i.e., meaning): expressions s, t may refer to the same entity while, at the same time, presenting that entity in different ways — whence s and t have different meanings.

Type
Chapter
Information
Intensionality , pp. 123 - 159
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2005

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

[1] J., Barwise and J., Perry, Situations and attitudes, MIT Press, Cambridge,Mass., 1983.
[2] M., Beeson, Foundations of constructive mathematics, Springer, New York, 1985.
[3] G., Boolos, The logic of provability, Cambridge UP, Cambridge, 1993.
[4] A. W., Burks, Chance, cause, reason, The University of Chicago Press, Chicago, London, 1963.
[5] S., Buss, First-order proof theory of arithmetic, Handbook of proof theory (S., Buss, editor), Elsevier, Amsterdam, 1998, pp. 79–147.
[6] R., Carnap, Der logische Aufbau der Welt, Meiner, Hamburg, 1928, Quotations are from The logical structure of the world, University of California Press, Berkeley, 1967.
[7] R., Carnap, Logische Syntax der Sprache, Springer, Wien, 1934, Quotations are from The logical syntax of language, Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1937.
[8] R., Carnap, Meaning and necessity, University of Chicago Press, Chicago, 1947.
[9] M., Cresswell, Structured meanings, MIT Press, Cambridge,Mass., 1985.
[10] D., Davidson, Inquiries into truth and interpretation, Clarendon Press, Oxford, 1984.
[11] M., Detlefsen, Hilbert's program, Reidel, Dordrecht, 1986.
[12] S., Feferman, Arithmetization of metamathematics in a general setting, FundamentaMathematicae, vol. XLIX (1960), pp. 35–92.
[13] S., Feferman, Autonomous transfinite progressions and the extent of predicative mathematics, Logic, methodology and philosophy of science III (B., van Rootselaar and J. F., Staal, editors), North-Holland, Amsterdam, 1968, pp. 121–135.
[14] S., Feferman, Constructive theories of functions and classes, Logic colloquium '78 (M., Boffa et al., editors), Springer, Berlin, 1979, pp. 159–224.
[15] S., Feferman, Intensionality in mathematics, The Journal of Symbolic Logic, vol. 14 (1985), pp. 41–55.Google Scholar
[16] G., Frege, Ü ber Sinn und Bedeutung, Zeitschrift fÜr Philosophie und philosophische Kritik, NF, vol. 100 (1892), pp. 25–50. Reprinted in G., Patzig (ed.): G. Frege: Funktion, Begriff, Bedeutung, Fünf logische Studien, Vandenhoeck and Ruprecht, Göttingen 1962, 40–65.
[17] K., Gödel, Eine Interpretation des intuitionistischen Aussagenkalküls, Ergebnisse eines mathematischen Kolloquiums, vol. 4 (1933), pp. 39–40.Google Scholar
[18] D., Guaspari and R. M., Solovay, Rosser sentences, Annals ofMathematical Logic, vol. 16 (1979), pp. 81–99.Google Scholar
[19] P., Hàjek and P., Pudlàk, Metamathematics of first-order arithmetic, Springer, Berlin, 1993.
[20] G., Hellman, Mathematics without numbers, Clarendon, Oxford, 1989.
[21] G., Hughes and M., Cresswell, A companion to modal logic, Methuen, London/New York, 1984.
[22] R., Kaye, Models of peano arithmetic, Clarendon Press, Oxford, 1991.
[23] S., Kripke, Semantical considerations on modal logic, Acta Philosophica Fennica, vol. 16 (1963), pp. 83–94.Google Scholar
[24] K., Kunen, Set theory, Elsevier, Amsterdam, 1980.
[25] C. I., Lewis and C. H., Langford, Symbolic logic, Century, New York, 1932.
[26] R. B., Marcus, Extensionality, Mind, vol. 69 (1960), pp. 55–62.Google Scholar
[27] Y., Moschovakis, Sense and denotation as algorithm an value, Logic colloquium '90 (J., Oikkonen and J., Väänänen, editors), Springer, Berlin, 1993.
[28] A., Mostowski, Thirty years of foundational studies, Blackwell, Oxford, 1966.
[29] K. G., Niebergall, “Natural” representations and extensions of Gödel's second theorem, forthcoming.
[30] K. G., Niebergall, Zur Metamathematik nichtaxiomatisierbarer Theorien, CIS,München, 1996.
[31] K. G., Niebergall, On the limits of Gödel's second incompleteness theorem, Argument und Analyse. proceedings of GAP4 (C. U., Moulines and K. G., Niebergall, editors), mentis, Paderborn, 2002, pp. 109–136.
[32] K. G., Niebergall and M., Schirn, Hilbert's programme and Gödel's theorems, Dialectica, vol. 56 (2002), pp. 347–370.Google Scholar
[33] H., Putnam, Mathematics without foundations, Journal of Philosophy, vol. 64 (1967), pp. 5–22.Google Scholar
[34] W. V. O., Quine, Notes on existence and necessity, Journal of Philosophy, vol. 40 (1943), pp. 113–127.Google Scholar
[35] W. V. O., Quine, Mathematical logic, revised ed., Harvard University Press, Cambridge, 1951.
[36] W. V. O., Quine, The problem of meaning in linguistics, From a logical point of view (W. V. O., Quine, editor), Harvard University Press, Cambridge,Mass., 1953, pp. 47–64.
[37] W. V. O., Quine, Reference and modality, From a logical point of view (W. V. O., Quine, editor), Harvard University Press, Cambridge,Mass., 1953, pp. 139–159.
[38] W. V. O., Quine, Word and object, M.I.T. Press, Cambridge,Mass., 1960.
[39] W. V. O., Quine, Ontological relativity, Ontological relativity and other essays, Columbia University Press, New York, 1969.
[40] B., Russell, An inquiry into meaning and truth, Unwin Paperbacks, London, 1950.
[41] S., Shapiro (editor), Intensional mathematics, North-Holland, Amsterdam, 1985.
[42] C., Smorynski, Consistency and related metamathematical properties, Technical Report 75–02, Mathematisch Instituut, Amsterdam, 1975.
[43] C., Smorynski, The incompleteness theorems, Handbook of mathematical logic (J., Barwise, editor), North-Holland, Amsterdam, 1977.
[44] C., Smorynski, Self-reference and modal logic, Springer, Berlin, 1985.
[45] A., Visser, Peano's smart children: a provability logical study of systems with built-in consistency, Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, vol. 30 (1989), pp. 161–196.Google Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×