Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-sjtt6 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-06-16T21:59:49.877Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

1 - Pragmatism, categories, and language

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 June 2014

Stephen Leach
Affiliation:
Keele University
James Tartaglia
Affiliation:
Keele University
Get access

Summary

Pragmatism is getting respectable again. Some philosophers are still content to think of it as a sort of muddle-headed first approximation to logical positivism – which they think of in turn as a prelude to our own enlightened epoch. But those who have taken a closer look have realized that the movement of thought involved here is more like a pendulum than like an arrow. This renewed interest in pragmatism has led to a new interest in Peirce, who somehow seems the most “up-to-date” of the pragmatists, and whose work in logic permits one to call him muddle-headed only if one is also willing to call him schizophrenic. But students of Peirce, even the most sympathetic, have had trouble digesting what he called his “Scotistic realism” and his categories of Firstness, Secondness, and Thirdness. These are obviously central features of his thought, yet they do not seem to sit well with his pragmatism. Still, Peirce insists over and over again that “the validity of the pragmatic maxim” and “Scotistic realism” mutually entail each other, and he suggests that they are both expressions of “the irreducibility of Thirdness.”

My purpose in this chapter is to try to show that the point Peirce is making in this identification is sound and important. Focusing on this point shows how far Peirce was in advance of the positivism of his day and how close his views are to the present trends in philosophy which have arisen in reaction to the more sophisticated positivism of Wittgenstein’s Tractatus and of the Vienna Circle. I want to suggest that Peirce’s thought envisaged, and repudiated in advance, the stages in the development of empiricism which logical positivism represented, and that it came to rest in a group of insights and a philosophical mood much like those we find in the Philosophical Investigations and in the writings of philosophers influenced by the later Wittgenstein.

Type
Chapter
Information
Mind, Language, and Metaphilosophy
Early Philosophical Papers
, pp. 16 - 38
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2014

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

White, Morton, Toward Reunion in Philosophy (Cambridge, MA, 1956), pp. 268ffGoogle Scholar
Pasch, Alan, Experience and the Analytic (Chicago, 1958)Google Scholar
Pears, D. F.’s article “Universals,” reprinted in Logic and Language, Second Series, ed. Flew, A. N. (Oxford, 1955)Google Scholar
Wittgenstein, ’s remark that “The use of the word ‘rule’ and the use of the word ‘same’ are interwoven.” (Philosophical Investigations [Oxford, 1953], No. 225.)Google Scholar
Hart, H. L. A., “The Ascription of Responsibility and Rights,” reprinted in Logic and Language, First Series (Oxford, 1951), pp. 145ffGoogle Scholar
Urmson, J. O., Philosophical Analysis (Oxford, 1956), ch. 10.Google Scholar
Firth, Roderick puts forward in “Sense-Data and the Percept Theory, Part II,” Mind, 59 (1950), pp. 34–55Google Scholar
Gentry, George in “Habit and the Logical Interpretant” (Studies in the Philosophy of Charles Sanders Peirce [Cambridge, MA, 1952], pp. 75ffGoogle Scholar
Stallknecht, N. P., “Decision and Existence,” Review of Metaphysics, 6 (1952), pp. 31ffGoogle Scholar
Sellars, Wilfrid’s “Concepts as Involving Laws and Inconceivable Without Them” (Philosophy of Science, 15 [1948], pp. 287–315)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goodman, Nelson, Fact, Fiction, and Forecast (Cambridge, MA, 1955), p. 117Google Scholar
Oliver, W. D.’s Theory of Order (Yellow Springs, 1951)Google Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×