To save content items to your account,
please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies.
If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account.
Find out more about saving content to .
To save content items to your Kindle, first ensure no-reply@cambridge.org
is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings
on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part
of your Kindle email address below.
Find out more about saving to your Kindle.
Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations.
‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi.
‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.
I have recently been working on a book about generating functions. It will be called ‘Generatingfunctionology,’ and it is intended to be an upper-level undergraduate, or graduate text in the subject. The object is to try to impress students with the beauty of this subject too, so they won't think that only bijections can be lovely.
In one section of the book I will discuss combinatorial identities, and the approach will be this. First I'll give the ‘Snake Oil’ method, in the spirit of a unified approach that works on many relatively simple identities. It involves generating functions. Second, I will write about a much more powerful method that works on ‘nearly all’ identities, including all classical hypergeometric identities and many, many binomial coefficient identities.
These two approaches will be mirrored here, in that this article will mostly be about the Snake Oil method, whereas the talk that I will give at the conference will be about the much more powerful method of WZ pairs [WZ], which at this writing is still under development. A brief summary of the WZ results appears in section (II) below.
Aside from these developments, there have been other unifying forces at work in the field of identities. The expository paper of Roy [Ro], shows how even without a computer one can recognize many binomial identities as cases of just a very few identities in the theory of hypergeometric series. The work of Knuth [Kn] shows how a few rules about binomial coefficients and their handling can, in skilled hands, prove many difficult identities.
Several years ago I was asked a seemingly innocuous question: What are the minimal-weight vectors of the code of an affine plane? I thought the answer would be that they were, just as in the projective case, simply the scalar multiples of the lines; indeed, that may be true and the question is still open. I managed to prove this (for arbitrary affine planes) only for those of prime order.
The question is deeper than it at first seems. If, for example, one could prove that the minimal-weight vectors of the code of an arbitrary affine plane were simply the scalar multiples of the lines, one would have a proof of the fact [15] that a projective plane of order ten has no ovals; indeed, one would prove that no projective plane of order congruent to two modulo four, except the Fano plane, could have an oval. (The minimal-weight vectors of the code of a desarguesian affine plane are the scalar multiples of the lines of the plane but the only known proof relies heavily on algebraic coding theory.)
These considerations led J. D. Key (who asked the original question) and me to what seems to be a fruitful approach to affine and projective planes and to what we hope will be a fruitful approach to the theory of designs. The purpose of this paper is to explain these matters. Much of the work we have done has already appeared and thus the present paper will rely heavily on four joint papers: Arcs and ovals in hermitian and Ree unitals, Affine and projective planes, Baer subplanes, ovals and unitals, and Translation planes and derivation sets.
Since its beginning in 1969 the British Combinatorial Conference has grown into an established international meeting. This year the twelfth conference is being held in Norwich under the auspices of the School of Mathematics at the University of East Anglia. Participants come from a great number of countries worldwide and represent a multitude of interests in combinatorial theory.
This volume contains the contributions of the principal speakers. They were invited to prepare a survey paper for this book and to deliver a lecture in an area of their expertise. In this way it is hoped to make available a valuable source of reference to the current state of art in combinatorics. The speakers have produced their papers well in advance so that they are now all available in time for the conference.
This book has been produced to a tight schedule. I am grateful to the authors for their cooperation and to the referees for their assistance and comments about the papers. The British Combinatorial Conference is largely selffinancing but on behalf of the committee I would like to thank the London Mathematical Society, Norwich Union and Peat Marwick McLintock for their financial support.
Every statistical design consists of two sets and a function between them. One set, T, consists of the treatments: they are under the experimenter's control, and the purpose of the experiment is to find out about them. The elements of the second set, Ω, are called plots for historical reasons. A plot is the smallest experimental unit to which an individual treatment is applied: it may or may not be a plot of land. In general the experimenter has less direct control over the attributes of the plots, and is not interested in finding out about the plots per se. Unless otherwise stated, Ω and T are always finite. Finally there is the design map ϕ from Ω to T which allocates treatments to plots; if treatment t is allocated to plot ω then ωϕ = t.
Typically one or both of the sets T and Ω is structured. I cannot give a formal definition of this concept, but examples of structures on a set include: a set of partitions; a transitive permutation group; a set of subsets; a graph; an association scheme. Many, but not all, of these structures can be specified as a set of (binary) relations with certain properties. A set will be said to be unstructured if the relations in its structure are just the equality relation E and the uncaring relation U (the direct square of the whole set) or U \ E.
A t–design S(λ; t, k, v) is a collection of k–subsets, called blocks, of a v-set S such that any t-subset of S is contained in exactly λ blocks. An S(λ; 2, k, v) is often called a (v, k, λ)-design and an S(λ; t, k, v) is often called a t-(v, k, λ)- design. An S(λ; t, k, v) is called simple if it contains no repeated blocks* It has been known for a long time that there are a lot of S(λ; t, k, v) for all t, see [6, 23]. However, until relatively recently, the only known examples of simple t-designs with t ≥ 6 were the trivial t-designs consisting of all k-subsets of a v-set. The first examples of non-trivial simple 6-designs were found by Magliveras and Leavitt [9]. In [19], we constructed nontrivlal simple t-designs for all t. It is not the purpose of this paper to give another proof of the main result of [19], as a simplified proof Is already given in [21]. Rather, we will survey construction techniques for t-designs using totally symmetric regular arrays, or, equlvalently, regular extended designs. These techniques played a major role in the construction of non-trivial simple t-designs for arbitrary t. We will point out the relationship between the techniques of [19, 21] and results of Wilson, Schreiber, Beth and Lu, as well as other results of the author and folklore direct product constructions.
This is the final paper of the series of three papers under the same title. The finite dimensional theory developed in the first of them 7 contains first of all:
(a) a calculus having among its consequences the calculi of convex subdifferentials and generalized gradients of Clarke (henceforth sometimes abbreviated C.g.g.) in the most general form which is partly due to the fact that in a finite dimensional space
for any convex function f and
for any SX (A means approximate, C means Clarke); and (b) a theorem stating that approximate subdifferentials are minimal (as sets) among all possible subdifferentials satisfying one or another set of conditions (usually very natural).
For a typical convex body in Ed a typical shadow boundary under parallel illumination has infinite (d - 2)-dimensional Hausdorff measurewhile having Hausdorff dimension d2.
By a well-known theorem of Szemerdi 8 any set of integers that has positive density contains arithmetic progressions of arbitrary length. One might expect that there are conditions of similar generality, under which an integer set contains arbitrarily long strings of consecutive integers, i.e., arithmetic progressions with 1 as common difference. Results of this kind would be of great importance because of potential applications to arithmetically interesting sets such as the set n: (n) = 1, where (n) is the Liouville function, or the sets
where P(n) denotes the greatest prime factor of n and 0<< 1. One naturally expects that such sets contain arbitrarily long strings of consecutive integers, but no results in this direction are known, and the problem seems to be a very difficult one, perhaps comparable in depth to the prime k-tuple conjecture.
The theorem of Aleksandrov-Fenchel-Jessen states that two convex bodies in n-dimensional Euclidean space En which, for some p l, , n - l 007D;, have equal area measures of order p (see Section 2 for a definition) differ only by a translation. Two independent proofs were given by Aleksandrov 1 and by Fenchel and Jessen 18 see also Busemann 5 (p. 70) and LeichtweiG 25 (p. 319), 26. If the boundaries of the two bodies are sufficiently smooth and of everywhere positive curvatures, then the assumption of the theorem is equivalent to saying that at points with parallel outer normals the p-th elementary symmetric functions of the principal radii of curvature of both boundary hypersurfaces are the same. For this case, Chern 6 gave a uniqueness proof by means of an integral formula.
The purpose of this paper is to take some first steps the investigation of the negative moments
where k>0 and12, and the related discrete moments
whereruns over the complex zeros of the zeta-function. We assume the Riemann hypothesis (RH) throughout; it then follows that Ik(, T) converges for every k > 0 when>but for no k =when =. We further note that Jk(T) is only defined for all T if all the zerosare simple and, in that case, Ik(, T) converges for all k<.
Ramsey's theorem implies that every function f:0, 1ℝ isconvex or concave on an infinite set. We show that there is an upper semicontinuous function which is not convex or concave on any uncountable set. We investigate those functions which are not convex on any r element set (r). A typical result: if f is bounded from below and is not convex on any infiniteset then there exists an interval on which the graph of f can be covered by the graphs of countably many strictly concave functions.