To save content items to your account,
please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies.
If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account.
Find out more about saving content to .
To save content items to your Kindle, first ensure no-reply@cambridge.org
is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings
on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part
of your Kindle email address below.
Find out more about saving to your Kindle.
Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations.
‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi.
‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.
Grundbegriffe der Wahrscheinlichkeitsrechnung by Andrei Kolmogorov is the book which has become the symbol of modern probability theory, its year of appearance 1933 being seen as a turning point that made earlier studies redundant. In mathematics, it is fairly common to take a field of study as given, as being defined by a set of commonly accepted postulates. Kolmogorov's presentation of probability in terms of measure theory serves well to illustrate this supposedly ahistorical character of mathematical research: With some knowledge of set theory, one can take the book, and learn and start doing probability theory. In such an approach, the concepts and the structure of probability theory appear fixed, whereas the experience of those who built up modern probability must have been very different. There were many kinds of approaches to the foundations of the subject. The idea of a measure theoretic foundation was almost as old as measure theory itself, and it had been repeatedly presented and used in the literature. Therefore the mere idea was not the reason for the acceptance of Kolmogorov's measure theoretic approach, but rather what he achieved by the use of measure theoretic probabilities. The change brought about by Kolmogorov was a big step, but not the kind of dramatic revelation some later comments suggest. The two essential mathematical novelties of Grundbegriffe were the theory of conditional probabilities when the condition has probability 0, and the general theory of random or stochastic processes.
FIRST STEPS IN MEASURE THEORETIC PROBABILITY. AXIOMATIZATION
Gyldér's problem in continued fractions
Measure theory originated at the end of the last century from problems encountered mainly in mathematical analysis, the theory of trigonometric series, and integration theory. Measure first was a generalization of geometric measure in Euclidean space. Current measure theory originated as an abstraction from making the concepts independent of real numbers and real spaces. This abstract kind of measure theory was first given in Fréchet (1915).
In Borel (1898) a generalization of length on the real line was proposed which is now called the Borel measure. The definition is repeated in Borel's first paper on probability (1905b): First measurable sets are defined as consisting of closed intervals, finite or denumerable unions of closed intervals, and complements relative to a given measurable set. The Borel measure of an interval [a, b] is b – a, that of a denumerable set of pairwise disjoint closed intervals the sum of the lengths of the intervals, and the measure of a complement E – F the measure of E minus that of F. If an arbitrary set E is contained in a measurable set A of measure α and contains a measurable set B of measure β, its measure m is less than or equal to α and greater than or equal to β.
Sheer curiosity led me to read more and more of the old literature on probability. These explorations resulted in a number of papers during the 1980s, and at a certain point it occurred to me that I should try to write down the results of my efforts in a systematic way. No one had pursued the background of modern probability in any detail, so that I felt free to let my own particular interests act as my guide. As a result, the emphasis here is on foundational questions.
A historical–philosophical colleague may find the references to secondary literature few in number. This is due to the fact that literature on the development of modern probability is truly scarce, and it is also due to my insistence on consulting all the primary sources in the first place. I also wanted to combine a useful bibliography of primary sources with manageable length. There should still be enough indications to allow the uninitiated to begin reading the secondary literature.
I am indebted to several institutions for support during the period of writing the book. Most important, a fellowship of the Academy of Finland has secured the continuity of my researches. In 1982, I had the good fortune of being invited to join the project ‘Probabilistic Revolution’ at the Zentrum für interdisziplinäre Forschung at Universitä Bielefeld.
The two main interpretive ideas about probability for the times under discussion are the frequentist and the subjectivist. Frequentist probability has had a remarkable role in the development of modern probability. It was the object of von Mises' theory, and it was more or less tacitly assumed as the interpretation of probability by the main proponents of mathematical probability in the 1920s. No attention was paid to the idea of subjective probabilities. The most one can find are Borel's philosophical essay (1924), which is a review of Keynes' Treatise on Probability of 1921, Borel's papers on game theory, and Lévy's discussion of subjective probability in his book of 1925. Borel's main contribution to probability (1909a), though, was from much earlier times.
The idea of subjective probabilities was further undermined by the developments in physics: Classical statistical physics already contained a commitment to statistical probability at least, and quantum mechanics brought a new kind of fundamental indeterminism into the description of nature's basic processes in 1926. An epistemic notion of probability must at that time have seemed like a thing from the past, from the shadows of the Laplacian doctrine of mechanical determinism.
In the 1920s philosophical thinking, or at least the part of it sensitive to scientific developments, was transformed through the rise of logical empiricism. Heisenberg's quantum mechanics of 1925 is one example of a scientific theory that shows the mutual effect of philosophical ideas and theory construction.
Richard von Mises was an applied mathematician. He first specialized in mechanics, hydrodynamics especially. By applied, he really meant it: A book of 1918, for example, dealt with the ‘elements of technical hydromechanics.’ Another related specialty was the theory of flight, much in vogue early on in the century. His work on probability starts properly around 1918, and from the same time are his first writings on foundational problems in science: on foundations of probability in 1919, and on classical mechanics in 1920. Von Mises' philosophical book Wahrscheinlichkeit, Statistik und Wahrheit of 1928 was the third volume in the Vienna Circle series ‘Schriften zur wissenschaftlichen Weltauffassung’, edited by Philipp Frank and Moritz Schlick. The year 1931 marked the publication of von Mises' big book on probability theory, Wahrschein-lichkeitsrechnung, whose exact title adds, ‘and its application in statistics and theoretical physics.’ The posthumous Mathematical Theory of Probability and Statistics is based on lectures from the early 1950s.
Von Mises was a declared positivist, identifying himself with the philosophy of the Berlin group, the Vienna Circle, and the Unity of Science Movement. His Kleines Lehrbuch des Positivismus (1939) appeared in an English version in 1951 as Positivism: A Study in Human Understanding. It attempts to give a broad presentation of the logical empiricist world view, from foundations of knowledge and the sciences to morals and society.
In this paper the Hausdorff dimension of systems of real linear forms which are simultaneously small for infinitely many integer vectors is determined. A system of real linear forms,
where ai, xij∈ℝ, 1 ≤i≤m, 1≤j≤n will be denoted more concisely as
where a∈⇝m, X∈ℝmn and ℝmn is identified with Mm × n(ℝ), the set of real m × n matrices. The supremum norm of any vector in k dimensional Euclidean space, ℝk will be denoted by |v|. The distance of a point a from a set B, will be denoted by dist (a, B) = inf {|a − b|: b ∈ B}.
We consider the fluid motion induced when a circular cylinder performs small-amplitude oscillations about an axis parallel to a generator to which it is rigidly attached as in Fig l(a). In common with other fluid flows dominated by oscillatory motion, a time-independent, or steady streaming develops, and this is the focus of our attention. In particular we relate our results, qualitatively, to the observations that have been made in experiments.
The analytic paracommutators in the periodic case have been studied. Their boundedness, compactness, the Schatten-von Neumann properties and the cut-off phenomena have been proved. These results have been applied to some kind of operators on the Bergman spaces that have cut-off at any p∈(0, ∞).
Norms with moduli of smoothness of power type are constructed on spaces with the Radon-Nikodym property that admit pointwise Lipschitz bump functions with pointwise moduli of smoothness of power type. It is shown that no norms with pointwise moduli of rotundity of power type can exist on nonsuperreflexive spaces. A new smoothness characterization of spaces isomorphic to Hilbert spaces is given.
In the case of F-isotropic groups for a global field F, Moore [Mo] computed the metaplectic kernel using crucially his theorem of uniqueness of reciprocity laws. For F-anisotropic G, a variant of Moore's theorem is, therefore, needed to compute the metaplectic kernel. Such a variant was announced by G. Prasad [GP1] (in 1986) and here we give the details.
Given a commutative semigroup (S, +) with identity 0 and u × v matrices A and B with nonnegative integers as entries, we show that if C = A – B satisfies Rado's columns condition over ℤ, then any central set in S contains solutions to the system of equations . In particular, the system of equations is then partition regular. Restricting our attention to the multiplicative semigroup of positive integers (so that coefficients become exponents) we show that the columns condition over ℤ is also necessary for the existence of solutions in any central set (while the distinct notion of the columns condition over Q is necessary and sufficient for partition regularity over ℕ\{1}).
The main object of this note is to prove that in three-space the sausage arrangement is the densest packing of four unit balls. Our method can be used to determine minimal arrangements with respect to various properties of four-ball packings, as we point out in Section 3.
We shall say that the sets A, B ⊂ Rk are equivalent, if they are equidecomposable using translations; that is, if there are finite decompositions and vectors x1,…, xd∈Rk such that Bj = Aj + xj, (j = 1,…,d). We shall denote this fact by In [3], Theorem 3 we proved that if A ⊂ Rk is a bounded measurable set of positive measure then A is equivalent to a cube provided that Δ(δA)<k where δA denotes the boundary of A and Δ(E) denotes the packing dimension (or box dimension or upper entropy index) of the bounded set E. This implies, in particular, that any bounded convex set of positive measure is equivalent to a cube. C. A. Rogers asked whether or not the set
Let |θ| < π/2 and . By refining Selberg's method, we study the large values of as t → ∞ For σ close to ½ we obtain Ω+ estimates that are as good as those obtained previously on the Riemann Hypothesis. In particular, we show that
and
Our results supplement those of Montgomery which are good when σ > ½ is fixed.
General expressions are found for the orthonormal polynomials and the kernels relative to measures on the real line of the form μ + Mδc, in terms of those of the measures dμ and (x − c)2dμ. In particular, these relations allow us to show that Nevai's class M(0, 1) is closed under adding a mass point, as well as obtain several bounds for the polynomials and kernels relative to a generalized Jacobi weight with a finite number of mass points.
In this paper we characterize Fountain-Gould left orders in abelian regular rings. Our first approach is via the multiplicative semigroups of the rings. We then represent certain rings by sheaves. Such representations lead us to a characterization of left orders in abelian regular rings such that all the idempotents of the quotient ring lie in the left order.