To save content items to your account,
please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies.
If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account.
Find out more about saving content to .
To save content items to your Kindle, first ensure no-reply@cambridge.org
is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings
on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part
of your Kindle email address below.
Find out more about saving to your Kindle.
Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations.
‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi.
‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.
Recursively presented topological spaces are topological spaces with a recursive system of basic neighbourhoods. A recursively enumerable (r.e.) open set is a r.e. union of basic neighbourhoods. A set is everywhere r.e. open if its intersection with each basic neighbourhood is r.e. Similarly we define everywhere creative, everywhere simple, everywhere r.e. non-recursive sets and show that there exist sets both with and without these everywhere properties.
Notions of effective complementation in effective topological spaces are considered, and several types of non-complemented sets are constructed. While there are parallels with recursively enumerable sets, some unexpected differences appear. Finally, a pair of splitting theorems is proved.
This paper attempts to classify the least ordinal α0 for which E(α0) (the E closure of α0 ∪ {α0}) is inadmissible. Among the result proved are (i)Lα0 = ZFC-; (ii)α0 is very large in comparison with the least ordinal satifying (i); (iii) (α0, α] marks precisely an ω-Gap, where α¯ = E(α0) ∩ ON; (iv) the Kr-sequence of α0 has length ω.
An infinite collection of indecomposable isols such that no isol is comparable to certain infinitary combinations of the others is constructed, extending a result of Dekker and Myhill. This collection is then used to investigate differences between the arithmetic of classical RET's and that of RET's on recursive manifolds, a difference relevant to the manifold equivalent of the Schröder-Bernstein Theorem.
Given a variety K of lattice-ordered algebras, A ∈ K is catalytic if for all B ∈ K, K(A, B) is a lattice for the pointwise order. The catalytic objects are determined for various varieties of distributive-lattice-ordered algebras. The characterisations obtained do not show an overall unity and exhibit diverse behaviour. Duality is employed extensively. Its usefulness in this context depends on the existence of an order-isomorphism between K(A, B) and the corresponding dual horn-set. Criteria for the existence of such an order-isomorphism are investigated for dualities of the Davey-Werner type. The relationship between catalytic objects and colattices is also discussed.
In 1981 two notions of effective presentation of countable connected graphs were formulated by J. C. E. Dekker—namely, edge recognition algorithm graphs and minimal path algorithm graphs. In this paper we show that every planar graph has a minimal path algorithm presentation but that some graphs have no minimal path algorithm presentations. We introduce the notion of a shortest distance algorithm graph, show that it lies strictly between the two notions of Dekker, and show that every graph has a shortest distance algorithm presentation. Finally, in contrast to Dekker's result about minimal path algorithm graphs, we produce a shortest distance algorithm graph which has no spanning tree which is an edge recognition algorithm graph.
In an elementary topos if R is a ring and X is a decidable object then there exists a canonical homomorphism from the coproduct of an X-family of R-modules to the product of the same family. In this paper it is shown that this homomorphisms is a monomorphism.
All inverse semigroups with idempotents dually well-ordered may be constructed inductively. The techniques involved are the constructions of ordinal sums, direct limits and Bruck-Reilly extensions.
We examine the concepts of nowhere simplicity in a wide class of abstract dependence systems. Initially we examine how many of the existing results valid for L(ω), the lattice of r.e. sets, have analogues valid for more general lattices. For example, we show that any r. e. subspace of V∞ can be decomposed into a pair of nowhere simple subspaces.
Algebras (A, ∧, ∨, ~, γ, 0, 1) of type (2,2,1,1,0,0) such that (A, ∧, ∨, ~, γ 0, 1) is a De Morgan algebra and γ is a lattice homomorphism from A into its center that satisfies one of the conditions (i) a ≤ γa or (ii) a ≤ ~ a ∧ γa are considered. The dual categories and the lattice of their subvarieties are determined, and applications to Lukasiewicz algebras are given.
For Γ a revursively enumerable set of formulae, a structure U on a recursive universe is said to be “Γ-recursively enumerable” if the satisfaction predicate restricted to Γ is recursively enumerable (equivalently, if the formulae of Γ uniformulae of Γ uniformly denote recursively enumerable relations on U).
For recursively enumerable sets Γ1 ⊆ Γ2 of formulae we shall, under certain conditions, characterize structures U with the following properties.
1) Every isomorphism form U to a Γ1-recursively enumerable structure is a recursive isomorphism.
2) Every Γ1-recursively enumerable structure isomorphic to U is recursively isomorphic to U.
3) Every Γ1-recursively enumerable structure isomorphic to U is Γ2-recursively enumerable.
Let the word “graph” be used in the sense of a countable, connected, simple graph with at least one vertex. We write Qn and Ocn for the graphs associated with the n-cube Qn and the n-octahedron Ocn respectively. In a previous paper (Dekker, 1981) we generalized Qn and Qn to a graph QN and a cube QN, for any nonzero recursive equivalence type N. In the present paper we do the same for Ocn and Ocn. We also examine the nature of the duality between QN and OcN, in case N is an infinite isol. There are c RETs, c denoting the cardinality of the continuum.
An infinite subset of ω is monotone (1–1) if every recursive function is eventually monotone on it (eventually constant on it or eventually 1–1 on it). A recursively enumerable set is co-monotone (co-1–1) just if its complement is monotone (1–1). It is shown that no implications hold among the properties of being cohesive, monotone, or 1–1, though each implies r-cohesiveness and dense immunity. However it is also shown that co-monotone and co-1–1 are equivalent, that they are properly stronger than the conjunction of r-maximality and dense simplicity, and that they do not imply maximality.
It is shown that no functor F exists from the category of sets with injections, to the category of algebraically closed fields of given characteristic, with monomorphisms, having the properties that for all sets A. F(A) is an algebraically closed field having transcendence base A and for all injections f. F(f) extends f. There does exist such a functor from the category of linearly-ordered sets with order monomorphisms.
An application to model-theory using the same methods is given showing that while the theory of algebraically closed fields is ω-stable, its Skolemization is not stable in any power.
In Section 1 below I describe two measures of the complexity of a binary relation. J The theorem says that these two measures never disagree very much. Both measures of complexity arose in connection with Saharon Shelah's notion [5] of a stable firstt order theory; Shelah showed in effect that one measure is finite, if, and only if, the other is finite too. This follows trivially from the theorem below. I confess my main aim was not to get the extra information which the theorem provides, but to eliminate Shelah's use of uncountable cardinals, which seemed strangely heavy machinery for proving a purely finitary result. Section 2 below explains the modeltheoretic setting.
A set mapping on pairs over the set S is a function f such that for each unordered pair a of elements of S,f(a) is a subset of S disjoint from a. A subset H of S is said to be free for f if x∉ f({y, z}) for all x, y, z from H. In this paper, we investigate conditions imposed on the range of f which ensure that there is a large set free for f. For example, we show that if f is defined on a set of size K+ + with always |f(a)| <k then f has a free set of size K+ if the range of f satisfies the k-chain condition, or if any two sets in the range of f have an intersection of size less than θ for some θ with θ < K.
An alternative approach is proposed to the basic definitions of the lassical lambda calculus. A proof is sketched of the equivalence of the approach with the classical case. The new formulation simplifies some aspects of the syntactic theory of the lambda calculus. In particular it provides a justification for omitting in syntactic theory discussion of changes of bound variable.