We use cookies to distinguish you from other users and to provide you with a better experience on our websites. Close this message to accept cookies or find out how to manage your cookie settings.
To save content items to your account,
please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies.
If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account.
Find out more about saving content to .
To save content items to your Kindle, first ensure no-reply@cambridge.org
is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings
on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part
of your Kindle email address below.
Find out more about saving to your Kindle.
Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations.
‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi.
‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.
If P is a partially ordered set and R is a commutative ring, then a certain differential graded R-algebra A•(P) is defined from the order relation on P. The algebra A•() corresponding to the empty poset is always contained in A•(P) so that A•(P) can be regarded as an A•()-algebra. The main result of this paper shows that if R is an integral domain and P and P′ are finite posets such that A•(P)≅A•(P′) as differential graded A•()-algebras, then P and P′ are isomorphic.
This paper studies higher dimensional analogues of the Tamari lattice on triangulations of a convex n-gon, by placing a partial order on the triangulations of a cyclic d-polytope. Our principal results are that in dimension d≤3, these posets are lattices whose intervals have the homotopy type of a sphere or ball, and in dimension d≤5, all triangulations of a cyclic d-polytope are connected by bistellar operations.
The random k-dimensional partial order Pk(n) on n points is defined by taking n points uniformly at random from [0,1]k. Previous work has concentrated on the case where k is constant: we consider the model where k increases with n.
We pay particular attention to the height Hk(n) of Pk(n). We show that k = (t/log t!) log n is a sharp threshold function for the existence of a t-chain in Pk(n): if k – (t/log t!) log n tends to + ∞ then the probability that Pk(n) contains a t-chain tends to 0; whereas if the quantity tends to − ∞ then the probability tends to 1. We describe the behaviour of Hk(n) for the entire range of k(n).
We also consider the maximum degree of Pk(n). We show that, for each fixed d ≧ 2, is a threshold function for the appearance of an element of degree d. Thus the maximum degree undergoes very rapid growth near this value of k.
We make some remarks on the existence of threshold functions in general, and give some bounds on the dimension of Pk(n) for large k(n).
Any preorder P on a set X has an associated preorder P′, P″, P‴, … The proerties of this sequence are studied. When X is finite the sequence is eventually periodic with period P = 1 or p = 1, the eventual constant preorder is full p = 2 the possible forms which the eventual alternating order can take are examined: first, the possible combinations of components are enumerated; second, the notion of ramification at a caste is used to show that X may in a heuristic sense be of unbounded complexity. If X is orderdense the periodicity starts at P′.
A new arrow notation is used to describe biordered sets. Biordered sets are characterized as biordered subsets of the partial algebras formed by the idempotents of semigroups. Thus it can be shown that in the free semigroup on a biordered set factored out by the equations of the biordered set there is no collapse of idempotents and no new arrows.
There is no single generalization of distributivity to semilattices. This paper investigates the class of mildly distributive semilattices, which lies between the two most commonly discussed classes in this area—weakly distributive semilattices and distributive semilattices. Particular attention is paid to describing and characterizing congruence distributive mildly distributive semilattices, in contrast to distributive semilattices, whose lattice of join partial congruences is badly behaved and which are difficult to describe.
A Hausdorff space X is said to be compactly generated (a k-space) if and only if the open subsets U of X are precisely those subsets for which K ∩ U is open in K for all compact subsets of K of X. We interpret this property as a duality property of the lattice O(X) of open sets of X. This view point allows the introduction of the concept of being quasicompactly generated for an arbitrary sober space X. The methods involve the duality theory of up-complete semilattices, and certain inverse limit constructions. In the process, we verify that the new concept agrees with the classical one on Hausdorff spaces.
By using the concept of tame embeddings of chains, a characterization is given of the subobjects of the lattice-ordered groups of order-automorphisms of the chains of rational and real numbers.
A semilattice tree T with 0 is slim if there is a chain C with 0 so that the lattices θ (T) and θ(C) of semilattice congruences are isomorphic. This paper establishes elementary consequences of slimness and uses simple constructive techniques to show certain small trees slim. If T is the union of at most countably many branches, each of which has a maximum or a countable cotinal subset, then T is slim. For trees with enough maximals slimness is equivalent with not having any uncountable anti-chains. If a tree T has a countable cofinal subset then T is slim. Thus finitary trees are slim.
If L is any semilattice, let TL denote the Munn semigroup of L, and Aut (L) the automorphism group of L.
We show that every semilattice L can be isomorphically embedded as a convex subsemilattice in a semilattice L' which has a transitive automorphism group in such a way that (i) every partial isomorphism α of L can be extended to an automorphism of L', (ii) every partial isomorphism: α: eL → fL of L can be extended to a partial isomorphism αL′: eL′ → fL′ of L′ such that TL → TL′, α → αL′ embeds TL' isomorphically in TL′, (iii) every automorphism γ of L can be extended to an automorphism γL′ of L′ such that Aut (L) → Aut (L′), γ → γL embeds Aut (L) isomorphically in Aut (L′).
Let P be a partially-ordered set in which every two elements have a common lower bound. It is proved that there exists a lower semilattice L whose elements are labelled with elements of P in such a way that (i) comparable elements of L are labelled with elements of P in the same strict order relation; (ii) each element of P is used as a label and every two comparable elements of P are labels of comparable elements of L; (iii) for any two elements of L with the same label, there is a label-preserving isomorphism between the corresponding principal ideals. Such a structure is called a full, uniform P-labelled semilattice.
An attempt is made to extend the theory of extensions of partial orders in groups to strict partially ordered N-groups. Necessary and sufficient conditions, for a strict partial order of an N-group to have a strict full extension, and for a strict partial order of an N-group to be an intersection of strict full orders, are obtained when the partially ordered near-ring N and the N-group G satisfy the condition (− x) n = − xn for all elements x in G and positive elements n in N.
A totally ordered set (and corresponding order-type) is said to be rigid if it is not similar to any proper initial segment of itself. The class of rigid ordertypes is closed under addition and multiplication, satisfies both cancellation laws from the left, and admits a partial ordering that is an extension of the ordering of the ordinals. Under this ordering, limits of increasing sequences of rigid order-types are well defined, rigid and satisfy the usual limit laws concerning addition and multiplication. A decomposition theorem is obtained, and is used to prove a characterization theorem on rigid order-types that are additively prime. Wherever possible, use of the Axiom of Choice is eschewed, and theorems whose proofs depend upon Choice are marked.